Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ndmmz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-23T19:26:41.470Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explicating Lawhood

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Peter Vallentyne*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy Virginia Commonwealth University

Abstract

D. M. Armstrong, Michael Tooley, and Fred Dretske have recently proposed a new realist account of laws of nature, according to which laws of nature are objective relations between universals. After criticizing this account, I develop an alternative realist account, according to which (1) the nomic structure of a world is a relation between initial world-histories and world-histories, and (2) a law of nature is a fact that holds solely in virtue of nomic structure (and not, for example, in virtue of past history).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1988 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I have benefited from the critical comments of David Armstrong, Bryson Brown, Philip Catton, Bill Demopoulos, Chris Gauker, Bill Harper, Patrick Maher, John Metcalfe, Rick Otte, Howard Sobel, Michael Tooley, Bas van Fraassen, and two anonymous referees for this journal. Research on this paper was supported by an internal grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada while I was at the University of Western Ontario.

References

REFERENCES

Armstrong, D. M. (1978), Universals and Scientific Realism, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. (1983), What is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. (1985), “Observation, Explanatory Power, and Simplicity: Toward a Non-Humean Account”, in P. Achinstein and O. Hannaway (eds.), Observation and Experiment in Modern Physical Science. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, pp. 4794.Google Scholar
Braithwaite, R. (1927), “The Idea of Necessary Connection”, Mind 36: 467477.10.1093/mind/XXXVI.144.467CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. (1977), “Laws of Nature”, Philosophy of Science 44: 248268.10.1086/288741CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, J. (1984), “Laws of Nature: The Empiricist Challenge”, in R. J. Bogdan (ed.), D. M. Armstrong. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, pp. 191223.10.1007/978-94-009-6280-4_8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, N. (1954), Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Athlone Press.Google Scholar
Harper, W., Stalnaker, R. and Pearce, G. (eds.) (1981), Ifs: Conditionals, Belief, Decision, Chance, and Time. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973), Counterfactuals. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1980), “A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance”, in W. Harper, R. Stalnaker, and G. Pearce (eds.) (1981), pp. 267–297; reprinted with addendum in D. Lewis (1986), pp. 83132.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983), “New Work for a Theory of Universals”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 343377.10.1080/00048408312341131CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986), Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McCall, S. (1969), “Time and the Physical Modalities”, Monist 53: 426446.10.5840/monist196953326CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCall, S. (1976), “Objective Time Flow”, Philosophy of Science 43: 337362.10.1086/288692CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCall, S. (1984), “Counterfactuals Based on Real Possible Worlds”, Noûs 18: 463477.10.2307/2215221CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montague, R. (1962), “Deterministic Theories”, in R. Thomason (ed.), Formal Philosophy. New Haven: Yale University Press (1974), pp. 303364. Originally published in Decisions, Values, and Groups 2. Oxford: Pergamon Press (1962), pp. 325–370.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1978), “Discussion: Dretske on Laws of Nature”, Philosophy of Science 45: 431439.10.1086/288817CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pargetter, R. (1984), “Laws and Modal Realism”, Philosophical Studies 46: 335347.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1968), The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 2nd edition. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1970), “On Properties”, in H. Putnam, Mathematics, Matter, and Method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1975), pp. 305322.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1980), Causal Necessity. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1984), Inquiry. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Swoyer, C. (1982), “The Nature of Natural Laws”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60: 203223.10.1080/00048408212340641CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, R. (1970), “Indeterminist Time and Truth Value Gaps”, Theoria 36: 264281.10.1111/j.1755-2567.1970.tb00427.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, R. (1984), “Combinations of Tense and Modality”, in D. Gabbay and F. Guenther (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, pp. 135165.10.1007/978-94-009-6259-0_3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, R., and Gupta, A. (1981), “A Theory of Conditionals in the Context of Branching Time”, in W. Harper, R. Stalnaker, and G. Pearce (eds.) (1981), pp. 299322.Google Scholar
Tooley, M. (1977), “The Laws of Nature”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 667698.10.1080/00455091.1977.10716190CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1981), “A Temporal Framework for Conditionals and Chance”, in W. Harper, R. Stalnaker, and G. Pearce, (eds.) (1981), pp. 323340.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (unpublished), “What are Laws of Nature?”.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (1983), An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar