Elsevier

Preventive Medicine

Volume 55, Issue 5, November 2012, Pages 405-408
Preventive Medicine

Heterogeneity of risk within racial groups, a challenge for public health programs

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ypmed.2012.08.022Get rights and content

Abstract

Targeting high-risk populations for public health interventions is a classic tool of public health promotion programs. This practice becomes thornier when racial groups are identified as the at-risk populations. I present the particular ethical and epistemic challenges that arise when there are low-risk subpopulations within racial groups that have been identified as high-risk for a particular health concern. I focus on two examples. The black immigrant population does not have the same hypertension risk as US-born African Americans. Similarly, Finnish descendants have a far lower rate of cystic fibrosis than other Caucasians. In both cases the exceptional nature of these subpopulations has been largely ignored by the designers of important public health efforts, including the recent US government dietary recommendations. I argue that amending the publicly-disseminated risk information to acknowledge these exceptions would be desirable for several reasons. First, recognizing low-risk subpopulations would allow more efficient use of limited resources. Communicating this valuable information to the subpopulations would also promote truth-telling. Finally, presenting a more nuanced empirically-supported representation of which groups are at known risk of diseases (not focusing on mere racial categories) would combat harmful biological race essentialist views held by the public.

Introduction

Public health interventions are often targeted to identifiable high-risk populations. This raises philosophical issues such as what it means for a population to be at risk and what ethical considerations should guide programs. These challenges become considerably more complex when the target populations are racial groups. As Troy Duster lays out in a 2006 paper on the use of race in medicine:

The unenviable task has been to try to walk a tightrope—to figure out a way to effectively deploy in research the concept of race (or population groups designated by race) without endowing “race” with a false sense of genetic essentialism (Duster, 2006, p. 488).

This danger is a quite real one, as misperceptions of the biological basis of race abound in the United States. More importantly, psychological data suggests, “[the] belief that social categories have an underlying nature/natural foundation” is one central basis for the formation and endorsement of stereotypes and prejudice” (Keller, 2005, pp. 686, 699). On the other hand, “this implies that one possible way of combating stereotyping and prejudice is to challenge the belief in genetic determinism and biological essentialism” (Keller, 2005, p. 699). The danger of promoting race essentialism (the view that racial categories demarcate deep intrinsic similarities among members of a race and corresponding differences between members of different races) does not automatically preclude the public application of race categories in medicine – Nancy Krieger has effectively argued why entirely ignoring race would “preclud[e] possibilities for monitoring progress and setbacks in reducing” “racial/ethnic inequalities” (2000, p. 213) – but that danger should be a guiding ethical consideration during deliberations about such medical uses.

I will show how information about racial groups' disease risks has been mishandled in two cases and make recommendations for ameliorating those missteps. In both cases, the designers of public health efforts have downplayed data that complicates their broad statements about racial groups being at elevated risk for particular diseases. I will focus on the black immigrant exception to the high rates of hypertension among African Americans and the Finnish exception to the high rates of cystic fibrosis among Caucasians. In these two cases there is ample data to support more nuanced (yet still simple and practical) characterizations of the at-risk populations—US-born African Americans are at elevated risk of hypertension and non-Finnish Caucasians are at elevated risk of cystic fibrosis. Yet, the unmodified racial categories continue to be used instead. This creates the unique situation in which low-risk subpopulations have had their interests marginalized during the propagation of broad claims about race-wide disease risks. Hence, we have two distinct problems that overlap in practice: the problem of ignoring low-risk islands within seas of high risk (so to speak) and the problem of privileging mere race when delineating which populations have public health risks. Together, the two problems combine to impede the dissemination of more nuanced data about heterogeneity of risk within racial groups.

I will argue that using available data to present more nuanced/specific representations of the relevant at-risk populations, beyond statements about racial groups broadly, would yield substantial benefits and also mitigate some of the harms associated with using race in medicine. Further nuance would preempt public overestimates of the biomedical significance of race, better serve the interests of the low-risk Finnish-descended and black immigrant subpopulations, improve the efficiency of public health resource usage (e.g. funds for testing people for recessive cystic fibrosis mutations) and promote truth-telling—the race-level data now provided is technically true, but is misleading for the low-risk subpopulations unless accompanied by the more nuanced available information. While I focus on analyzing the two aforementioned cases, the analysis suggests that more attention to low-risk subpopulations is warranted and that the privileging of data at the level of broad racial categories is an important obstacle to pursuing more nuanced representations of the heterogeneity of risk within racial categories.

Section snippets

The problem of heterogeneity of risk

Katherine Frohlich and Louise Potvin raise the problem of within-population heterogeneity of risk in their critique of Geoffrey Rose's influential “population strategy” of public health programs, which emphasizes small reductions of harm across entire populations, rather than large reductions of harm within limited high-risk subpopulations, the “high-risk strategy” (Frohlich and Potvin, 2008, Rose, 1992). It is beyond the scope of this paper to address the general merits of Rose's approach or

Dietary salt among African Americans

The joint U.S. Department of Agriculture and Health and Human Services publication Dietary Guidelines for Americans 2010 recommends a reduced-sodium diet for all African Americans, responding to a large body of data identifying the group as having relatively high risk of hypertension and its various cardiovascular sequelae, including stroke (Read et al., 2005).

Reduce daily sodium intake to less than 2300 milligrams (mg) and further reduce intake to 1500 mg among persons who are 51 and older and

Cystic fibrosis risk among Finnish descendants

During debates over the benefits and drawbacks of using race in medicine, discussion almost always focuses on minority or underprivileged groups. Indeed, this is a good thing. However, misapplications of blunt racial categories can also harm white residents of the United States or Europe. Whiteness/Caucasianness is no less hazy a category than African Americanness, so it should come as no surprise that misapplications of the Caucasian racial category in medicine can lead to serious problems. In

Choosing a level of specificity

Any demand for recognition of a further level of specificity in delineating a public health target population invites two important questions: 1) why increase the level of specificity beyond its current level? and 2) why stop at this level of specificity and not some other level? The first question has several answers.

Increasing the specificity of at-risk population characterizations corrects the misleading, though not technically false, risk assessments communicated to low-risk subpopulations.

Conclusion

Mere race has been treated as a privileged level of specificity in defining cardiovascular disease risk and cystic fibrosis risk. This is quite unfortunate. Of all the possible levels of population specificity, race is probably the choice that introduces the most unintended harm, primarily due to its tacit reinforcement of biological race essentialism. Adding one more level of specificity beyond mere race would leave the target population delineations simple enough to be accessible to laypeople

Conflict of interest statement

The author declares there is no conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

I have been greatly aided by feedback from Jim Nelson, Lisa Lloyd, Ryan Ketcham, Andrea Smith, Kristie Dotson, the participants of the 2012 UT-Dallas Science-Policy Interactions and Social Values Conference and this journal's two anonymous reviewers.

References (19)

  • M. Radhakrishnan et al.

    Economic evaluation of cystic fibrosis screening: a review of the literature

    Health Policy

    (2008)
  • F. Calafell et al.

    The Molecular Genetic Epidemiology of Cystic Fibrosis: Report of a Joint Meeting of WHO/ECFTN/ICF(M)A/ECFS Genoa, Italy, 19 June 2002 World Health Organization

    (2004)
  • Committee on Genetics

    Update on carrier screening for cystic fibrosis

    Obstet. Gynecol.

    (2011)
  • T. Duster

    Lessons from history: why race and ethnicity have played a major role in biomedical research

    J. Law Med. Ethics

    (2006)
  • K.L. Frohlich et al.

    Transcending the known in public health practice—the inequality paradox: the population approach and vulnerable populations

    Am. J. Public Health

    (2008)
  • J.M. Kaplan

    When socially determined categories make biological realities: understanding black/white health disparities in the U.S.

    Monist

    (2010)
  • J.S. Kaufman et al.

    The slavery hypertension hypothesis: dissemination and appeal of a modern race theory

    Epidemiology

    (2003)
  • J. Keller

    In genes we trust: the biological component of psychological essentialism and its relationship to mechanisms of motivated social cognition

    J. Pers. Soc. Psychol.

    (2005)
  • J. Kere et al.

    Cystic fibrosis in Finland: a molecular and genealogical study

    Hum. Genet.

    (1989)
There are more references available in the full text version of this article.

Cited by (18)

  • Ethics and policy issues for stem cell research and pulmonary medicine

    2015, Chest
    Citation Excerpt :

    Confidentiality can be particularly important when conducting stem cell research on genetic and/or rare conditions. In research on hereditary conditions, or where the genetic or familial basis of a disorder is suspected but not confirmed, potential donors may have concerns about genetic discrimination, the possibility of genetic results being returned (and the related biopsychosocial implications of these results for donors as well as family members), and the implications for carrier screening.37–40 Given scientific interest in using stem cells to model pathogenesis for many types of lung diseases (such as ARDS, newborns with hereditary lung conditions, and interstitial lung disease), there is a desire to obtain, store, and share biospecimens from affected individuals.

  • Culture(s)

    2012, Preventive Medicine
  • Philosophical issues in cancer and public health

    2022, The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Public Health
  • Race and racism in public health

    2022, The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Public Health
View all citing articles on Scopus
View full text