Skip to main content
Log in

Exhaustivity In Dynamic Semantics; Referential And Descriptive Pronouns

  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I argue that anaphoric pronouns should always be interpreted exhaustively. I propose that pronouns are either used referentially and refer to the speaker's referents of their antecedent indefinites, or descriptively and go proxy for the description recoverable from its antecedent clause. I show how this view can be implemented within a dynamic semantics, and how it can account for various examples that seemed to be problematic for the view that for all unbound pronouns there always should be a notion of exhaustivity/uniqueness involved. The uniqueness assumption for the use of singular pronouns is also shown to be importantto explain what the discourse referents used in dynamic semantics represent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Chastain, C.: 1975, 'Reference and Context', in K. Gunderson (ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. VII - Language, Mind and Knowledge, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G.: 1992, 'Anaphora and Dynamic Binding', Linguistics and Philosophy 15, 111–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G.: 1996, Dynamics of Meaning, Anaphora, Presuppositions and the Theory of Grammar, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R.: 1979, 'The Interpretation of Pronouns', in F. Heny and H. S. Schnelle (eds.), Selections from the Third Groningen Round Table, Syntax and Semantics, 10, Academic Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dekker, P.: 1993, Transsentential Meditations, PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam.

  • Dekker, P.: 1996, 'The Values of Variables in Dynamic Semantics', Linguistics and Philosophy 19, 211–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dekker, P.: 1997, 'On First Order Information Exchange', in A. Benz and G. Jaeger (eds.), Proceedings of Mundial' 97. Munich Workshop on the Formal Semantics and Pragmatics of Dialogue, CIS, München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dekker, P. and R. van Rooy: 1998, 'Intentional Identity and Information Exchange', in R. Cooper and T. Gamkrelidze (eds.), Proceedings of the Second Tbilisi Symposium on Language, Logic and Computation, Tbilisi State University.

  • Does, J. van der: 1994, 'Formalising E-type Logic', in P. Dekker and M. Stokhof (eds.), Proceedings of the Ninth Amsterdam Colloquium, Amsterdam, pp. 229–248.

  • Donnellan, K.: 1978, 'Speaker Reference, Descriptions, and Anaphora', in P. Cole (ed.), Syntax and Semantics, vol. 9: Pragmatics, New York: Academic Press, pp. 47–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G.: 1979, 'Pronouns, Quantifiers and Relative Clauses (1)', The Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7, 467–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernando, T.: 1995, 'Are Context Change Potentials Functions?' in H. Kamp and B. Partee (eds.), Context in the Analysis of Linguistic Meaning, Stuttgart/Prague.

  • Fodor, J. and I. Sag: 1982, 'Referential and Quantificational Indefinites', Linguistics and Philosophy 5, 355–398.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraassen, B. van: 1967, 'Meaning Relations Among Predicates', Nous 1, 161–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G.: 1985, The Metaphysics of Modality, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerbrandy, J. and W. Groeneveld: 1997, 'Reasoning About Information Change', Journal for Language, Logic and Information 6, 147–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J. and M. Stokhof: 1990, 'Dynamic Montague Grammar', in: L. Kalman and L. Polos (eds.), Papers from the Second Symposium on Logic and Language, Budapest, Academia Kiado.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J. and M. Stokhof: 1991, 'Dynamic Predicate Logic', Linguistics and Philosophy 14, 39–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., M. Stokhof, and F. Veltman: 1996, 'Coreference and Modality', in Lappin (ed.), Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory, Oxford, Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I.: 1982, The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I.: 1990, 'E-type Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora', Linguistics and Philosophy 13, 137–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heusinger, K. von: 1997, 'The Reference on Indefinites', in K. von Heusinger and U. Egli (eds.), Reference and Anaphoric Relations, Kluwer, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H.: 1981, 'A Theory of Truth and Semantic Representation', in Groenendijk et al. (eds.), Formal Methods in the Study of Language, pp. 277–322, Amsterdam.

  • Kamp, H.: 1988, 'Comments on Robert Stalnaker: “Belief Attribution and Context”', in R. Grimm and D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought, Tuscon, University of Arizona Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H.: 1990, 'Prolegomena to a Structural Account of Belief and Other Attitudes', in R. Grimm and D. Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought, Tuscon, University of Arizona Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H. and U. Reyle: 1993, From Discourse to Logic, Kluwer, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D.: 1989, 'Demonstratives', in I. Almog et al. (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, Oxford University Press.

  • Krahmer, E. and R. Muskens: 1995, 'Negation and Disjunction in Discourse Representation Theory', Journal of Semantics 12, 357-376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S.: 1977, 'Speakers Reference and Semantic Reference', Midwest Studies in Philosophy II, 255–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.: 1979, 'Scorekeeping in a Language Game', Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 339–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R.: 1974, 'Pragmatics', in R. Thomason (ed.), Formal Philosophy, Yale University Press, New Haven, pp. 95–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neale, S.: 1990, Descriptions, MIT Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B.: 1989, 'Binding Implicit Variables in Quantified Contexts', in Papers from the 25th Regional Meeting: Parasession on Language in Context, Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago.

  • Quine, W. V.: 1960, Word and Object, Cambridge, MA.

  • Rooy, R. van: 1997, Attitudes and Changing Contexts, PhD thesis, University of Stuttgart.

  • Rooy, R. van: 2000, 'Anaphoric Relations Across Attitude Contexts', in K. von Heusinger and U. Egli (eds.), Reference and Anaphoric Relations, Kluwer, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, F.: 1982, The Logic of Natural Language, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R.: 1970, 'Pragmatics', Synthese 22, 272–289.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R.: 1978, 'Assertion', in P. Cole (ed.), Syntax and Semantics, vol. 9: Pragmatics, pp. 315–332, Academic Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R.: 1998, 'On the Representation of Context', Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 7, 3–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.: 1952, Introduction to Logical Theory, Methuen, London.

  • Zimmermann, T. E.: 1998, 'Remarks on the Epistemic Role of Discourse Referents', in L. Moss (ed.), Logic, Language and Computation, Vol. 2, CSLI publications, Stanford.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Van Rooy, R. Exhaustivity In Dynamic Semantics; Referential And Descriptive Pronouns. Linguistics and Philosophy 24, 621–657 (2001). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1017597801178

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1017597801178

Keywords

Navigation