Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T11:25:52.670Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Some reflections on Husserlian intentionality, intentionalism, and non-propositional contents

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Corijn van Mazijk*
Affiliation:
University of Groningen, The Netherlands KU Leuven, Belgium

Abstract

This paper discusses Husserl’s theory of intentionality and compares it to contemporary debates about intentionalism. I first show to what extent such a comparison could be meaningful. I then outline the structure of intentionality as found in Ideas I. My main claims are that – in contrast with intentionalism – intentionality for Husserl (i) covers just a region of conscious contents; that it is (ii) essentially a relation between act-processes and presented content; and that (iii) the side of act-processes contains non-representational contents. In the third part, I show that Husserl also (iv) offers resources against intentionalism’s exclusive concern with propositional content.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Literature

Bayne, T. 2010. The Unity of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199215386.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 1994. “Peacocke's Argument Against the Autonomy of Nonconceptual Representational Content.” Mind and Language 9: 402418. 10.1111/mila.1994.9.issue-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 1995. “Nonconceptual Content: From Perceptual Experience to Subpersonal Computational States.” Mind and Language 10 (4): 333369.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2011. “Nonconceptual mental content.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, E.. http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2003/entries/content-nonconceptual/.Google Scholar
Bourget, D. 2015. “Representationalism, Perceptual Distortion and The Limits of Phenomenal Concepts.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (1): 1636. 10.1080/00455091.2014.981932CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bower, M. 2014. “Affectively Driven Perception: Toward a Non-representational Phenomenology.” Husserl Studies 30: 225245. doi:10.1007/s10743-014-9152-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1): 73121. 10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. 1986. “Cartesian Error and the Objectivity of Perception”. In Foundations of Mind: Philosophical Essays (vol. 2). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. 2001. “Intentionalism Defended.” Philosophical Review 110 (2): 199240. 10.1215/00318108-110-2-199CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carman, T. 1999. “The Body in Husserl and Merleau-Ponty.” Philosophical Topics 27 (2): 205226. 10.5840/philtopics199927210CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, T. 1988. “The Waterfall Illusion.” Analysis 48 (3): 142147. 10.1093/analys/48.3.142CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, T. 1992. “The Nonconceptual Content of Experience.” In The Contents of Experience, edited by Crane, T.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511554582CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, T. 1998. “Intentionality as the Mark of the Mental.” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 43: 229251. 10.1017/S1358246100004380CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, T. 2003. “The Intentional Structure of Consciousness.” In Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Jokic, A. and Smith, Q., 3356. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crane, T. 2006. “Brentano’s Concept of Intentional Inexistence.” In The Austrian Contribution to Analytic Philosophy, edited by Textor, M., 2035. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Crane, T. 2009. “Intentionalism.” In Oxford Handbook to the Philosophy of Mind, edited by Beckermann, A. and McLaughlin, B., 474493. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crane, T. 2014. Aspects of Psychologism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 10.4159/harvard.9780674726581CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowell, S. 2013. Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9781139548908CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doyon, M. 2015. “Perception and Normative Self-Consciousness.” In Normativity in Perception, edited by Doyon, M. and Breyer, T., 3855. Basingstoke: Palgrave. 10.1057/9781137377920CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Drummond, J. 1992. “An Abstract Consideration: De-Ontologizing the Noema.” In The Phenomenology of the Noema, edited by Drummond, J. and Embree, L., 89110. Dordrecht: Springer Science + Business Media, B. V. 10.1007/978-94-017-3425-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Follesdal, D. 1969. “Husserl’s Notion of Noema.” The Journal of Philosophy 66 (20): 680687. 10.2307/2024451CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gurwitsch, A. 2010. “The Field of Consciousness: Theme, Thematic Field, and Margin.” In Works of Aron Gurwitch (1901–1973) (vol. III), edited by Van Breda, H. L., 221287. Dordrecht: Springer. 10.1007/978-90-481-3346-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. 1990. “The Intrinsic Quality of Experience.” Philosophical Perspectives 4: 3152. 10.2307/2214186CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. 1960. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. Translated by Cairns, D.. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. 1974. “Kant and the Idea of Transcendental Philosophy.” Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 5 (3): 956. 10.5840/swjphil19745335CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. 1970. In The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Translated by Carr, D.. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. 1977. Phenomenological Psychology: Lectures, Summer Semester, 1925. Translated by Scanlon, J.. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. 10.1007/978-94-010-1083-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. 1980. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy: Third Book: Phenomenology and the Foundation of the Sciences. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. 10.1007/978-94-009-8779-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. 1983. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy: First Book: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology. Translated by Kersten, F.. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. 1997. Experience and Judgment: Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. 2000. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy: Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Translated by Rojcewicz, R. and Schuwer, A.. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. 2002. Einleitung in die Philosophie: Vorlesungen 1922/23. Husserliana XXXV, edited by Bernet, R. and Melle, U.. Dordrecht: Springer Science + Business Media B.V.Google Scholar
Jansen, J. 2015. “Transcendental Philosophy and the Problem of Necessity in a Contingent World.” Metodo: International Studies in Phenomenology and Philosophy 1 (1): 4780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, U. 2007. “Intentional Inexistence and Phenomenal Intentionality.” Philosophical Perspectives 21 (1): 307340. 10.1111/phpe.2007.21.issue-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, B. 1988. “Social Content and Psychological Content.” In Contents of Thought, edited by Grimm, R. and Merrill, D., 99110. Tucson, AZ: University of Arizona Press.Google Scholar
Loar, B. 1990. “Phenomenal States.” Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 4, Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind, 81108.Google Scholar
Lohmar, D. 2003. “Husserl’s Type and Kant’s Schemata.” In The New Husserl: A Critical Reader, edited by Welton, D., 93124. Bloomington, IL: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Lohmar, D. 2014. “Types and Habits: Habits and Their Cognitive Background in Hume and Husserl.” Phenomenology and Mind 6: 4863.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 2001. “The Case for Phenomenal Externalism.” Philosophical Perspectives 15: 1735.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. 2015. “Representational Theories of Consciousness.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, E. N.. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-representational/.Google Scholar
Marcelle, D. 2011. “The Phenomenological Problem of Sense Data in Perception: Aron Gurwitsch and Edmund Husserl on the Doctrine of Hyletic Data.” Investigaciones Fenomenológicas 8: 6176. 10.5944/rif.8.2011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marcus, E. 2006. “Intentionalism and the Imaginability of the Inverted Spectrum.The Philosophical Quarterly 56 (224): 321339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, M. G. F. 2002. “The Transparency of Experience.” Mind and Language 17 (4): 376425. 10.1111/mila.2002.17.issue-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. H. 1994. “The Content of Perceptual Experience.” The Philosophical Quarterly 44 (175): 190205. 10.2307/2219740CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. H. 1996. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. H. 2009. Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. H. 2013. “The Myth of the Mind as Detached.” In Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: the McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, edited by Schear, J. K., 4158. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McIntyre, R., and Smith, D. W.. 1989. “Theory of Intentionality.” In Husserl’s Phenomenology: a Textbook, edited by Mohanty, J. N. and McKenna, W., 147179. Washington, DC: University Press of America.Google Scholar
McKenna, W. R. 1984. “The Problem of Sense Data in Husserl’s Theory of Perception.” In Edmund Husserl: Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers, edited by Bernet, R., Welton, D., and Zavota, G., 145158. Oxon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Mohanty, J. N. 1992. “Noema and Essence.” In The Phenomenology of the Noema, edited by Drummond, J. and Embree, L., 4956. Dordrecht: Springer Science + Business Media, B. V.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, D. 2000. “Heidegger’s Critique of Husserl’s and Brentano’s Account of Intentionality.” Inquiry 43: 3965. 10.1080/002017400321361CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, D. 2011. “Edmund Husserl’s Phenomenology of Habituality and Habitus.” Journal of the British Society of Phenomenology 42 (1): 4377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, D. 2014. “The Ego as Substrate of Habitualities: Edmund Husserl’s Phenomenology of the Habitual Self.” Phenomenology and Mind 6: 2647.Google Scholar
Nickel, B. 2006. “Against Intentionalism.” Philosophical Studies 136 (3): 279304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pace, M. 2007. “Blurred Vision and the Transparency of Experience.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88: 328354. 10.1111/papq.2007.88.issue-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peacocke, C. 2001a. “Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content?The Journal of Philosophy 98 (5): 239264. 10.2307/2678383CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peacocke, C. 2001b. “Phenomenology and Nonconceptual Content”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.” LXII (3): 609615.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 2002. “Sensation and the Content of Experience: A Distinction.” In Vision and Mind, edited by Noë, A. and Thompson, E., 267288. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Preston, B. 1994. “Husserl’s Non-Representational Theory of Mind.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 32 (2): 209232. 10.1111/sjp.1994.32.issue-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975. “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’.” In Philosophical Papers, Volume 2: Mind Language and Reality, 215271. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schellenberg, S. 2011. “Perceptual Content Defended.” Noûs 45 (4): 714750.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seager, W., and Bourget, D.. 2007. “Representationalism about Consciousness.” In The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, edited by Velmans, M. and Schneider, S., 261276. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing. 10.1002/9780470751466.ch21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1998. “Ten Problems of Consciousness.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (3): 671678. 10.2307/2653767CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 2000. “Phenomenal Character Revisited.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2): 6567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Speaks, J. 2005. “Is There a Problem about Nonconceptual Content?Philosophical Review 114 (3): 359398. 10.1215/00318108-114-3-359CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, D. 2007. “The Consequences of Intentionalism.” Erkenntnis 66 (1): 247270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toribio, J. 2007. “State Versus Content: The Unfair Trial of Perceptual Nonconceptualism.” Erkenntnis 69: 351361. 10.1007/s10670-008-9120-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2002. “Representationalism and the Transparancy of Experience.” Noûs 36: 137151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Mazijk, C. 2015. “Do We Have To Choose between Conceptualism and Non-Conceptualism?International Journal of Philosophical Studies 23 (5): 645665. 10.1080/09672559.2015.1091028CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Mazijk, C. 2016. “Kant and Husserl on the Contents of Perception.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 54 (2): 267287. 10.1111/sjp.2016.54.issue-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willard, D. 1992. “Finding the Noema.” In The Phenomenology of the Noema, edited by Drummond, J. and Embree, L., 2949. Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media, B. V.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahavi, D. 2004. ““Husserl’s noema and the internalism-externalism debate”. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary.” Journal of Philosophy 47 (1): 4266.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. 2008. “Internalism, externalism, and transcendental idealism.” Synthese 160: 355374. 10.1007/s11229-006-9084-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar