Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The criticism of medicine at the end of its “golden age”

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Medicine is increasingly subject to various forms of criticism. This paper focuses on dominant forms of criticism and offers a better account of their normative character. It is argued that together, these forms of criticism are comprehensive, raising questions about both medical science and medical practice. Furthermore, it is shown that these forms of criticism mainly rely on standards of evaluation that are assumed to be internal to medicine and converge on a broader question about the aim of medicine. Further work making medicine’s internal norms explicit and determining the aim of medicine would not only help to clarify to what extent the criticism is justified, but also assist an informed deliberation about the future of medicine. To illustrate some of the general difficulties associated with such a task, the paper concludes by critically engaging Edmund Pellegrino’s account of the aim of medicine as well as the Hastings Center’s consensus report.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The exact temporal boundaries of the “golden age” are not drawn consistently in the literature. Some maintain that the golden age comprises the first half of the twentieth century; others hold that it characterizes a period after World War II (see [3]); and still others associate it with the “conquest” of epidemic infectious disease [5].

  2. Some of McKeown’s most forceful claims were based on studying mortality decline in England and Wales. Since then, researchers have pointed to similar examples during the mid-twentieth century (China 1949–1979, Cuba 1959–1979) where medicine has played only a minor role in mortality decline compared to improvements in housing, sanitation, and education [6].

  3. Indeed, EBM—stressing that clinical decisions ought to be made on the basis of the best available evidence of effectiveness—is in part motivated by recognizing that the history of medicine is dominated by harmful or ineffective interventions.

  4. The equation states that the probability of H given the evidence is equal to the prior probability of H, multiplied by the probability of E given the hypothesis, divided by the prior probability of E. The probability of H given E, P(H|E), depends on: (i) the prior probability of H being true, irrespective of the evidence (i.e., P(H)); (ii) the probability of the evidence given the hypothesis (i.e., P(E|H)); and (iii) the prior probability of E, irrespective of the hypothesis (i.e., P(E)).

  5. Some distinguish between criticism and critique, taking the former to refer to something less elaborated and directed toward persons and the latter to refer to a more developed consideration of a subject. However, this distinction is ambiguous and not used systematically in the literature. For example, in his discussion of criticism in science and philosophy, Karl Popper consistently speaks of “criticism,” even though the way he uses the terms fits the definition of critique [35]. For this reason, I will use “criticism” in a broad sense, which includes instances of critique.

  6. It is not clear, however, that practices can be said to be governed by rules. Drawing on Wittgenstein’s work on rule-following, some have argued that rules as more or less adequate representations of aspects of practices that are primary to the rules. Rules cannot keep participants in practices “on the rails” of the practice. Being able to comprehend what it is to follow a rule might require a prior conception of practice.

  7. An institution is not itself structured by the aim and norms of the practice it organizes, but in terms of practice-external goods (e.g., status, money, power) [34, p. 194]. Because institutions have a tendency to separate from the practice they sustain, the pursuit of two kinds of goods constitutes a source of potential conflict. For Alasdair MacIntyre, without virtues (e.g., justice, truthfulness) practices would not be able to withstand the corrupting power that institutions exert. This is problematic not only because the aims of practices are not achieved. There is much more at stake, because practices are the vehicles through which the common good and the potential of human beings is actualized.

  8. This is often referred to as “immanent criticism” in the literature, particularly in the tradition of critical theory (see [37]). I will not observe this additional distinction for the sake of simplicity.

  9. While Pellegrino’s account is particularly helpful when it comes to illustrating some general difficulties, there are of course other accounts available, such as the one proposed by Alex Broadbent [13]. Moreover, there are also other “list approaches”—or “consensual” approaches (see Schramme [39])—that proceed by cataloguing several aims, put forward by Howard Brody and Franklin G. Miller, Bengt Brülde, and Christopher Boorse.

References

  1. O’Mahony, Seamus. 2019. After the golden age: What is medicine for? Lancet 393: 1798–1799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. O’Mahony, Seamus. 2020. Can medicine be cured? The corruption of a profession. London: Head of Zeus.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Porter, Roy. 2002. Blood and guts: A short history of medicine. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Farmer, Paul, Matthew Basilico, and Luke Messac. 2016. After McKeown: The changing roles of biomedicine, public health, and economic growth in mortality declines. In Therapeutic revolutions: Pharmaceuticals and social change in the twentieth century, ed. Jeremy A. Greene, Flurin Condrau, Elizabeth Siegel Watkins, 186–217. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  5. DeWalt, Darren A., and Theodore Pincus. 2003. The legacies of Rudolf Virchow: Cellular medicine in the 20th century and social medicine in the 21st century. IMAJ 5: 395–397.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Kernahan, Peter J. 2012. Was there ever a “golden age” of medicine? Minnesota Medicine 95(9): 41–45.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ackerknecht, Erwin H. 1953. Rudolf Virchow: Doctor, statesman, anthropologist. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. McKeown, Thomas. 1976. The modern rise of population. London: Edward Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Zola, Irving Kenneth. 1972. Medicine as an institution of social control. Sociological Review 20: 487–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Illich, Ivan. 1974. Medical nemesis. Lancet 1: 918–921.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Illich, Ivan. 1975. Medical nemesis: The expropriation of health. London: Calder and Boyars.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Rothman, David J. 2017. Strangers at the bedside: A history of how law and bioethics transformed medical decision making. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. Broadbent, Alex. 2019. Philosophy of Medicine. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Porter, Roy. 1997. The greatest benefit to mankind: A medical history of humanity. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Wootton, David. 2006. Bad medicine: Doctors doing harm since Hippocrates. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ioannidis, John P.A.. 2005. Why most published research findings are false. PLOS Medicine 2(8): e124. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Ioannidis, John P.A.. 2011. An epidemic of false claims. Scientific American 304(6): 16–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Stegenga, Jacob. 2018. Medical nihilism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Parens, Eric. 2013. On good and bad forms of medicalization: On good and bad forms of medicalization. Bioethics 27(1): 28–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Scott, Susie. 2006. The medicalisation of shyness: From social misfits to social fitness. Sociology of Health and Illness 28: 133–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Moynihan, Ray, and Alan Cassels. 2005. Selling sickness: How the world’s biggest pharmaceutical companies are turning us all into patients. New York: Nation Books.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Conrad, Peter. 2005. The shifting engines of medicalization. Journal of Health and Social Behavior 46: 3–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Fanu, Le., and James. 2012. The rise and fall of modern medicine. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Marcum, James A. 2012. Medicine’s crises. In The virtuous physician, 1–28. Dordrecht: Springer.

  25. Weatherall, David. 1996. Science and the quiet art: The role of medical research in health care. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cassell, Eric J. 2004. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  27. Carel, Havi. 2017. Illness and its experience: The patient perspective. In Handbook of the philosophy of medicine, ed. Thomas Schramme and Steven Edwards, 93–108. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  28. Engelhardt, H. Tristram., Jr., and Fabrice Jotterand, eds. 2008. The philosophy of medicine reborn: A Pellegrino reader. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Berglund, Mia, Lars Westin, Rune Svanström, and Annelie Johansson Sundler. 2012. Suffering caused by care—Patients’ experiences from hospital settings. International Journal of Qualitative Studies on Health and Well-Being 7(1): 1–9. https://doi.org/10.3402/qhw.v7i0.18688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Kauppinen, Antti. 2002. Reason, recognition, and internal critique. Inquiry 45: 479–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Jaeggi, Rahel. 2018. Critique of forms of life, trans. Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

  32. Haslanger, Sally. 2018. What is a social practice? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 82: 231–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2007. After virtue: A study in moral theory, 3rd ed. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Popper, Karl R. 1983. Realism and the aim of science: From the postscript to the logic of scientific discovery, ed W.W. Bartley III. London: Routledge.

  36. Brandom, Robert B. 1994. Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Stahl, Titus. 2013. What is immanent critique? SSRN Electronic Journal.

  38. Pellegrino, Edmund D. 2001. The internal morality of clinical medicine: A paradigm for the ethics of the helping and healing professions. Journal of Medicine and 26: 559–579.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Schramme, Thomas. 2017. Goals of medicine. In Handbook of the philosophy of medicine, ed. Thomas Schramme and Steven Edwards, 121–128. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  40. Pellegrino, Edmund D., and David C. Thomasma. 1981. A philosophical basis of medical practice: Toward a philosophy and ethic of the healing professions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Pellegrino, Edmund D., and David C. Thomasma. 1993. The virtues in medical practice. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Callahan, Daniel (ed.). 1996. The goals of medicine: Setting new priorities. Hastings Center Report 26(6): S1–S28.

  43. Boorse, Christopher. 2016. Goals of medicine. In Naturalism in the philosophy of health, ed. Élodie. Giroux, 145–177. Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by a research Grant from the Carlsberg Foundation (CF19-0350).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Somogy Varga.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Varga, S. The criticism of medicine at the end of its “golden age”. Theor Med Bioeth 43, 401–419 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-022-09598-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-022-09598-9

Keywords

Navigation