Skip to main content
Log in

Agential thinking

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In his 2009 monograph, Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection, Peter Godfrey-Smith accuses biologists of demonstrating ‘Darwinian Paranoia’ when they engage in what he dubs ‘agential thinking’. But as Daniel Dennett points out, he offers neither an illuminating set of examples nor an extended argument for this assertion, deeming it to be a brilliant propaganda stroke against what is actually a useful way of thinking. Compared to the dangers of teleological thinking in biology, the dangers of agential thinking have unfortunately rarely been discussed. Drawing on recent work by Samir Okasha, I attempt to remedy this omission, through analyzing the nature of agential thinking, and providing a philosophical treatment of the unexamined dangers in this peculiar, yet tempting way of thinking.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Which is not to say that metaphors don’t play important roles in science (see Veit and Ney 2021).

  2. See Dennett’s From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds (2017, p. 34).

  3. See Veit (forthcomingb) for a recent essay review.

  4. Indeed, agential language is found throughout his recent monograph Other Minds: The Octopus, the Sea, and the Deep Origins of Consciousness (2016b). It will hardly be surprising that many see a close connection between the evolution of agency and consciousness (see Ginsburg and Jablonka 2019; Browning and Veit 2021; Veit 2021b, forthcoming a), but this topic is beyond the scope of this paper.

  5. See Millikan (1984); Neander (1983).

  6. The English language is unfortunately ambiguous in its use of the term ‘reason’ between these contexts.

  7. See Dennett (1995).

  8. The allure of this ‘stance’ will be target of Sect. 3.

  9. See Veit (2018) for an earlier discussion of mine of these different responses to the nature of ‘purpose’ by Dennett and Rosenberg.

  10. Dennett (2016) regards a rigid anti-teleological stance as a conceptual mistake.

  11. It is worth noting that when Godfrey-Smith discusses agential thinking, he unfortunately restricts himself to a criticism of the selfish gene point of view—a view he has several problems with that go beyond those related to agential thinking.

  12. Naturally, much the same can be said for genes and groups, both of which are sometimes treated as agents in their own right.

  13. Simple agent-based models for evolutionary dyamics of say social behaviour can be intepreted both culturally and genetically (Veit 2019c).

  14. See for example: Thaler (2015), Sugden (2015), Kahneman and Tversky (1979), and Loewenstein (1999).

  15. See Veit (2019a).

  16. A point vigorously defended by Dennett (2017).

  17. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this point.

  18. A variety of alternative mutations allows for this phenotype.

  19. But as Hammerschmidt et al. (2014) argue, it is not meaningful to speak here of a Darwinian individual in its own right, unless it has some way of reproduction. See also Okasha (2006) and Godfrey-Smith (2009).

  20. See also Davies (2004).

  21. Assuming one did not reach the summit in a snow-storm and is hence unable to see anything beyond a one meter radius.

  22. In a forthcoming paper, I argue that we can understand natural selection itself as an ecologically scaffolded process (see Veit forthcomingc).

  23. See for instance Veit (2019b, c).

References

  • Allen, C., & Neal, J. (2020). Teleological notions in biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

  • Brosnan, S. F., & De Waal, F. B. (2002). A proximate perspective on reciprocal altruism. Human Nature, 13(1), 129–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browning, H., & Veit, W. (2021). Evolutionary biology meets consciousness: essay review of Simona Ginsburg and Eva Jablonka’s The Evolution of the Sensitive Soul. Biology and Philosophy, 36(5), 1–11. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-021-09781-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability University of Chicago Press. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. Volume 163, pp. 163–228

  • Cushman, F. (2020). Rationalization is rational. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 43.

  • Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection. John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (2004). Epistemic entitlement, warrant transmission and easy knowledge. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 78, 213–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, J. (2010). Anthropomorphism in science. EMBO Reports, 11(10), 721–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R., et al. (1986). The blind watchmaker: Why the evidence of evolution reveals a universe without design. WW Norton & Company.

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The Selfish Gene: 30th Anniversary Edition–with a new Introduction by the Author (3 ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2011). Homunculi rule: Reflections on Darwinian populations and natural selection by Peter Godfrey Smith. Biology & Philosophy, 26(4), 475–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2019). Clever evolution. Metascience, 28(3), 355–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2013). The evolution of reasons. In B. Bashour & H. D. Muller (Eds.), Contemporary philosophical naturalism and its implications (pp. 47–62). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2016). Darwin and the overdue demise of essentialism. In D. Livingstone Smith (Ed.), How biology shapes philosophy: new foundations for naturalism, pp. 9–22.

  • Dennett, D. C. (2017). From bacteria to Bach and back: The evolution of minds. WW Norton & Company.

  • Dennett, D. C. (1971). Intentional systems. The Journal of Philosophy, pp. 87–106.

  • Fiegna, F., Yuen-Tsu, N. Y., Kadam, S. V., & Velicer, G. J. (2006). Evolution of an obligate social cheater to a superior cooperator. Nature, 441(7091), 310–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francis, R. C. (2004). Why men won’t ask for directions. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, A. (2009). Adaptation as organism design. Biology Letters, 5(6), 861–864.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, A. (2019). The agent concept is a scientific tool. Metascience, 28(3), 359–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E. (2019). The evolution of the sensitive soul: Learning and the origins of consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016a). Mind, matter, and metabolism. The Journal of Philosophy, 113(10), 481–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016b). Other minds: The octopus, the sea, and the deep origins of consciousness. Farrar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2017b). The subject as cause and effect of evolution. Interface Focus, 7(5), 20170022.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2017a). The evolution of consciousness in phylogenetic context. In K. Andrews & J. Beck (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of animals minds (pp. 216–226). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2020). Metazoa: Animal minds and the Birth of consciousness. Harper Collins.

  • Graziano, M. S. (2016). Consciousness engineered. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23(11–12), 98–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig, D. (2012). The strategic gene. Biology & Philosophy, 27(4), 461–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammerschmidt, K., Rose, C. J., Kerr, B., & Rainey, P. B. (2014). Life cycles, fitness decoupling and the evolution of multicellularity. Nature, 515(7525), 75–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F., & Simmel, M. (1944). An experimental study of apparent behavior. The American Journal of Psychology, 57(2), 243–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, pp. 263–291.

  • Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant) (P. Guyer, Ed.; E. Matthews, Trans.).

  • Kennedy, J. S. (1992). The new anthropomorphism. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kennett, J., & Matthews, S. (2003). The unity and disunity of agency. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 10(4), 305–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. (1999). Experimental economics from the vantage-point of behavioural economics. The Economic Journal, 109(453), F25–F34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx, K. (1861). Letter to F. Lassalle, 16 January 1861. Marx Engels Archive. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1861/letters/61_01_16-abs.htm.

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Price, G. R. (1973). The logic of animal conflict. Nature, 246(5427), 15–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1994). Typological versus population thinking. Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology, pp. 157–160.

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1983). Abnormal psychobiology. Ph. D. thesis, Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Bundoora, Australia: La Trobe University.

  • New England Anti-Vivisection Society, American Anti-Vivisection Society, The Physicians Committee for Responsible Medicine, The Humane Society of the United States, Humane Society Legislative Fund, J. Jacquet, B. Franks, J. Pungor, J. Mather, P. Godfrey-Smith, L. Marino, G. Barord, C. Safina, H. Browning, and W. Veit (2020). Petition to Include Cephalopods as “Animals” Deserving of Humane Treatment under the Public Health Service Policy on Humane Care and Use of Laboratory Animals. Harvard Law School Animal Law & Policy Clinic, pp. 1–30. https://doi.org/10.13140/RG.2.2.27522.30401.

  • Okasha, S. (2006). Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2018). Agents and goals in evolution. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2019, August). Reply to Dennett, Gardner and Rubin. Metascience 28(3), 373–382.

  • Patten, M. M. (2019). The X chromosome favors males under sexually antagonistic selection. Evolution, 73(1), 84–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pradeu, T. (2011). The limits of the self: Immunology and biological identity. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rainey, P. B., & Kerr, B. (2010). Cheats as first propagules: A new hypothesis for the evolution of individuality during the transition from single cells to multicellularity. BioEssays, 32(10), 872–880.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2013). Disenchanted Naturalism. In B. Bashour & H. D. Muller (Eds.), Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism and its Implications (pp. 17–36). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2011). The atheist’s guide to reality: Enjoying life without illusions. New York: WW Norton & Company.

  • Sellars, W. (1963). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. In Science, perception and reality, pp. 1–40. Routledge & Kegan Paul London.

  • Sellars, W. (2007). In the Space of Reasons: Selected Essays of Wilfrid Sellars. Harvard University Press.

  • Sterelny, K. and P. E. Griffiths (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago Press.

  • Sugden, R. (2015). Looking for a psychology for the inner rational agent. Social Theory and Practice, 41(4), 579–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarnita, C. E. (2017). The ecology and evolution of social behavior in microbes. Journal of Experimental Biology, 220(1), 18–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H. (2015). Misbehaving: The making of behavioral economics. WW Norton New York.

  • Veit, W. (2018). Existential nihilism: The only really serious philosophical problem. Journal of Camus Studies. https://doi.org/10.13140/RG.2.2.26965.24804

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veit, W. (2019a). Evolution of multicellularity: Cheating done right. Biology & Philosophy, 34(3), 34. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9688-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veit, W. (2019b). Model pluralism. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 50(2), 91–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veit, W. (2019c). Modeling morality. In Angel Nepomuceno-Fernándéz, L. Magnani, F. J. Salguero-Lamillar, C. Barés-Gémez, and M. Fontaine (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology, pp. 83–102. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-32722-4_6.

  • Veit, W. (2021a). Biological normativity: A new hope for naturalism? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-020-09993-w

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veit, W. (2021b). Health, agency, and the evolution of consciousness. Ph.D. thesis, University of Sydney. Manuscript in preparation.

  • Veit, W. (2021c). Review of Nancy Cartwright’s nature, the artful modeler: Lectures on laws, science, how nature arranges the world and how we can arrange it better. Philosophy of Science, 88(2), 366–369. https://doi.org/10.1086/711505

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veit, W., Dewhurst, J., Do-lega, K., Jones, M., Stanley, S., Frankish, K., & Dennett, D. C. (2019). The rationale of rationalization. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 43, 53. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/b5xkt

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veit, W., & Ney, M. (2021). Metaphors in arts and science. European Journal for Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00351-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veit, W., & Browning, H. (2020). Two kinds of conceptual engineering. Preprint. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/17452/

  • Veit, W. (forthcomingc). Scaffolding Natural Selection. Biological Theory.

  • Veit, W. (forthcomingb). Samir Okasha’s Philosophy. Lato Sensu: revue de la Société de philosophie des sciences.

  • Veit, W. (forthcominga). Consciousness, Complexity, and Evolution. Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

  • Walsh, D. M. (2015). Organisms, agency, and evolution. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weibull, J. W. (1995). Evolutionary Game Theory. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2005). Genes and the agents of life: The individual in the fragile sciences biology. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Samir Okasha, Heather Browning, Andy Gardner, two anonymous reviewers, and finally the Theory and Method in Biosciences group at the University of Sydney for their feedback on my manuscript.

Funding

This research was supported under Australian Research Council's Discovery Projects funding scheme (Grant No. FL170100160).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Walter Veit.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Veit, W. Agential thinking. Synthese 199, 13393–13419 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03380-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03380-5

Keywords

Navigation