Skip to main content
Log in

Carl Hempel's Philosophy of Science: How to Avoid Epistemic Discontinuity and Pedagogical Pitfalls

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Mathematical theories are essential for explanations in physics, chemistry andengineering. These theories often incorporate functions that are defined by theirrelation to other variables in the theory but not with reference to experimentalobservations. The wave function in quantum mechanics is perhaps one of thebest known example of such function, even though classical theories also providemany examples of such functions. These functions, which seem to hang in thin airdisconnected to experimental data, offer a daunting challenge to the instructor. Inthis article we consider the epistemic status of such functions and a method ofintroducing them to the students, a method that does not distort the original theory.We build our model for explanation on Hempel's analysis of relation between theoryand experiment and refine it further to show their roles in concept formation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Brush, S.G.: 1974, 'Should the History of Science be Rated X?', Science 183(4130), 1164-1172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P.A.B.: 1972, Fields and Quanta 3(2), 139-164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R.P., Leighton, R.B. &; Sands, M.: 1965, The Feynman Lectures on Physics, Vol. 3, p. 1-1, Addison-Wesley, Reading.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, P.: 1947, 'The Place of Philosophy of Science in the Curriculum of the Physics Student', American Journal of Physics 15(3), 202-218. Reprinted in his Modern Science and its Philosophy, Harvard University Press, Harvard, 1950, pp, 228–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G.: 1956, Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay, R.B. &; Margenau, H.: 1936, Foundations of Physics, John Wiley &; Sons, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matzkin, A.: 2002, 'Realism and the Wavefunctions', European Journal of Physics 23(3), 285-294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oxtoby, D.W., Gilles, H.P. &; Nachtrieb, N.H.: 1999, Principles of Modern Chemistry, 4th ed., Saunders College Publishing, Fort Worth, Texas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. &; Bratman, M. (eds.): 1993, Introduction to Philosophy, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rukeyser, M.: 1964, Willard Gibbs, Dutton, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E.R.: 2000, 'The Failure of Reduction and How to Resist Disunity of Sciences in the Context of Chemical Education', Science and Education 9(5), 405-425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E.R.: 2000, 'On Recently Claimed Observation of Atomic Orbitals and Some Related Philosophical Issues', Philosophy of Science (Supplement) 68(3), 76-89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vemulapalli, G.K.: 1993, Physical Chemistry, Prentice-Hall, Englewood-Cliffs, N.J.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, H.M.: 2001, 'Developing Intuitive Understanding of Free Energy', Journal of Chemical Education 78(10), 1362-1364.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, S.E. &; Battino, R.: 2001, 'Explaining Entropy Pictorially', Journal of Chemical Education 78(3), 311-312

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Vemulapalli, G.K., Byerly, H.C. Carl Hempel's Philosophy of Science: How to Avoid Epistemic Discontinuity and Pedagogical Pitfalls. Science & Education 13, 85–98 (2004). https://doi.org/10.1023/B:SCED.0000018498.92528.16

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/B:SCED.0000018498.92528.16

Keywords

Navigation