Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4hhp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-05T20:08:46.053Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Trials of Life: Natural Selection and Random Drift

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Denis M. Walsh
Affiliation:
University of Edinburgh
Tim Lewens
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
André Ariew*
Affiliation:
University of Rhode Island
*
Send requests for reprints to the authors. Walsh: Department of Philosophy, University of Edinburgh, David Hume Tower, George Square, Edinburgh, Scotland EH26 9NJ; Lewens: Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge, Free School Lane, Cambridge, UK CB2 3RH; Ariew: Department of Philosophy, 170 Chaffee Building, University of Rhode Island, Kingston, RI USA, 02881.

Abstract

We distinguish dynamical and statistical interpretations of evolutionary theory. We argue that only the statistical interpretation preserves the presumed relation between natural selection and drift. On these grounds we claim that the dynamical conception of evolutionary theory as a theory of forces is mistaken. Selection and drift are not forces. Nor do selection and drift explanations appeal to the (sub-population-level) causes of population level change. Instead they explain by appeal to the statistical structure of populations. We briefly discuss the implications of the statistical interpretation of selection for various debates within the philosophy of biology—the ‘explananda of selection’ debate and the ‘units of selection’ debate.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

We wish to thank the following for help and discussion. Alexander Bird, Anjan Chakravartty, Kent Holsinger, Deborah Kohn, Peter Lipton, Joel Pust, Alex Rosenberg, various members of the Philosophy Workshop, HPS, University of Cambridge, attendees at the ISHPSSB conference in Quinnipiac. We would like to acknowledge the invaluable comments offered by Elliott Sober. We would also like to thank the Seven Stars Bakery in Providence, Rhode Island for all the coffee and for not minding all the noise. We reserve especial thanks to R. C. Lewontin, for inspiration, hospitality, and support. Some of the ideas in this paper converge on those expressed in Matthen and Ariew (2002). These were developed largely independently.

References

Ariew, André (1998), “Are Probabilities Necessary for Evolutionary Explanations?”, Are Probabilities Necessary for Evolutionary Explanations? 13:245253.Google Scholar
Beatty, John (1984), “Chance and Natural Selection”, Chance and Natural Selection 51:183211.Google Scholar
Beatty, John (1992), “Random Drift”, in Keller, E. F. and Lloyd, E. (eds.), Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 273281.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert (1990), Adaptation and Environment. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cain, Arthur J. (1951), “So-called Non-adaptive or Neutral Characters in Evolution”, So-called Non-adaptive or Neutral Characters in Evolution 168: 424.Google ScholarPubMed
Crow, James, and Kimura, Mooto (1970), An Introduction to Population Genetics Theory. Minneapolis: Burgess Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, Richard (1976), The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, Richard (1982), The Extended Phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky Theodosius, Francisco Ayala, and Stebbins, G. Ledyard (1977), Evolution. San Francisco: Freeman.Google Scholar
Endler, John A. (1986), “Natural Selection in the Wild”, Princeton Ecological Monographs. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd et al. (1989), The Empire of Chance: How Probability Changed Science and Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewens, Tim (2001), “Sex and Selection: A Reply to Matthen”, Sex and Selection: A Reply to Matthen 52:589598.Google Scholar
Lewens, Tim (2001), Organisms and Artefacts: Design in Nature and Elsewhere. PhD. Dissertation. Cambridge: University of Cambridge.Google Scholar
Lewontin, Richard C. (1970), “The Units of Selection”, The Units of Selection 1:114.Google Scholar
Lewontin, Richard C. (1983), “Darwin’s Revolution”, Darwin’s Revolution 30:2127.Google Scholar
Lewontin, Richard C. (1974), “The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change”, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Matthen, Mohan (1999), “Evolution, Wisconsin Style: Selection and the Explanation of Individual Traits”, Evolution, Wisconsin Style: Selection and the Explanation of Individual Traits 50:143150.Google Scholar
Matthen, Mohan, and Ariew, André (2002), “Two Ways of Thinking about Fitness”, Two Ways of Thinking about Fitness 49(2): 5583.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, John (1986), Evolutionary Genetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Susan, and Beatty, John (1979), “The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness”, The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness 46:263286.Google Scholar
Millstein, Roberta (1996), “Random Drift and the Omniscient Viewpoint”, Random Drift and the Omniscient Viewpoint 63 (suppl.): S10S18.Google Scholar
Neander, Karen (1995), “Explaining Complex Adaptations: A Reply to Sober’s Reply to Neander”, Explaining Complex Adaptations: A Reply to Sober’s Reply to Neander 46:583587.Google Scholar
Pust, Joel (2001), “Natural Selection Explanation and Origin Essentialism”, Natural Selection Explanation and Origin Essentialism 31:201220.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alexander (1994), Instrumental Biology or the Disunity of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alexander (2001), “Discussion Note: Indeterminism, Probability, and Randomness in Evolutionary Theory”, Discussion Note: Indeterminism, Probability, and Randomness in Evolutionary Theory 68:536544.Google Scholar
Sklar, Lawrence (1999), “The Reduction(?) of Thermodynamics to Statistical Mechanics”, The Reduction(?) of Thermodynamics to Statistical Mechanics 95:187202.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1984), The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1993), Philosophy of Biology. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1995), “Natural Selection and Distributive Explanation: A Reply to Neander”, Natural Selection and Distributive Explanation: A Reply to Neander 46:384397.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2001), “The Two Faces of Fitness”, in Singh, R., Paul, Diane, Crimbas, Costas, and Beatty, John (eds.), Thinking about Evolution: Historical, Philosophical and Political Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 309321.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott, and Lewontin, Richard C. (1982), “Artifact, Cause and Genic Selection”, Artifact, Cause and Genic Selection 49:157180.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott and Wilson, David Sloan (1994), “A Critical Review of Philosophical Work on the Units of Selection Problem”, A Critical Review of Philosophical Work on the Units of Selection Problem 61:534555.Google Scholar
Sterelny, Kim, and Kitcher, Philip (1988), “The Return of the Gene”, The Return of the Gene 85:339360.Google Scholar
Walsh, Denis (1998), “The Scope of Selection: Neander and Sober on What Natural Selection Explains”, The Scope of Selection: Neander and Sober on What Natural Selection Explains 76:250264.Google Scholar
Walsh, Denis (2000), “Chasing Shadows: Natural Selection and Adaptation”, Chasing Shadows: Natural Selection and Adaptation 31:135153.Google Scholar
Waters, C. Kenneth (1991), “Tempered Realism about the Forces of Selection”, Tempered Realism about the Forces of Selection 58:553573.Google Scholar
Williams, George C. (1966), Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Yablo, Steven (1992), “Mental Causation”, Mental Causation 101:245280.Google Scholar