Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-10T11:42:06.447Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

DILEMMA ARGUMENTS AGAINST NATURALISM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 November 2013

Abstract

Albert Casullo (2000, 2003) and Shane Oakley (2011) argue that dilemma arguments against epistemic naturalism, such as those offered by Laurence BonJour (1998) and Harvey Siegel (1984), are such that, whatever strength they have against naturalism applies equally to moderate rationalist accounts of a priori justification. They conclude that dilemma arguments are, therefore, insufficient for establishing an advantage for moderate rationalism over naturalized epistemology. I argue that both Casullo's and Oakley's criticisms depend on an illicit assumption, namely, that dilemma arguments presuppose a meta-justificatory demand that naturalists provide non-circular support for their basic sources of evidence. I argue that this assumption is not necessary for the force of dilemma arguments, and I construct a version that avoids this misreading. I conclude that, although there remain strategies for responding to dilemma arguments, they constitute a challenge naturalists must take seriously.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Almeder, R. 1998. Harmless Naturalism. Peru, IL: Open Court Publishing.Google Scholar
Antony, L. 2004. ‘A Naturalized Approach to the A Priori.’ Philosophical Issues, 14: 117.Google Scholar
Bealer, G. 1993. ‘The Incoherence of Empiricism.’ In Wagner, S. J. and Warner, R. (eds), Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal, pp. 121–42. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Bealer, G. 1996. ‘A Priori Knowledge and the Scope of Philosophy.’ Philosophical Studies, 81: 121–42.Google Scholar
Bealer, G. 2000. ‘A Theory of the A Priori.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 81: 130.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. 1998. In Defense of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. and Sosa, E. 2003. Epistemic Justification: Internalism vs. Externalism, Foundations vs. Virtues. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Brown, H. I. 2011. ‘Epistemological Empiricism.’ In Shaffer, M. J. and Veber, M. L. (eds), What Place for the A Priori?, pp. 137–56. Chicago, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Casullo, A. 2000. ‘The Coherence of Empiricism.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 81: 3148.Google Scholar
Casullo, A. 2003. A Priori Justification. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. 1977. Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edn.Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 2005. ‘There is No A Priori.’ In Steup, M. and Sosa, E. (eds), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, pp. 105–15. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Forrest, P. 1996. God without the Supernatural: A Defense of Scientific Theism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R. N. 1999. Science without Laws. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1983. The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1985. ‘A Priori Knowledge.’ In Kornblith, H. (ed.), Naturalizing Epistemology, pp. 129–45. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 2000. ‘A Priori Knowledge Revisited.’ In Boghossian, P. and Peacocke, C. (eds), New Essays on the A Priori, pp. 6591. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. 1985. ‘Beyond Foundationalism and the Coherence Theory.’ In Kornblith, H. (ed.), Naturalizing Epistemology, pp. 115–28. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. 1993. Inductive Inference and Its Natural Ground. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. 2002. Knowledge and its Place in Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Oakley, S. 2011. ‘A Dilemma for Naturalized Epistemology?’ In Shaffer, M. J. and Veber, M. L. (eds) What Place for the A Priori?, pp. 157175. Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing.Google Scholar
Oshana, M. 1994. ‘Autonomy Naturalized’. In French, P. A., Uehling, T. E. Jr. and Wetstein, H. K. (eds), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. XIX, Philosophical Naturalism, pp. 7694. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. 2011. ‘The Philosophical Insignificance of A Priori Knowledge.’ In Shaffer, M. J. and Veber, M. L. (eds), What Place for the A Priori?, pp. 6183. Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1993. Warrant and Proper Function. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rea, M. 2002. World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roth, P. 1980. ‘Theories of Nature and the Nature of Theories.’ Mind, 79: 431–8.Google Scholar
Roth, P. 1983. ‘Siegel on Naturalized Epistemology and Natural Science.’ Philosophy of Science, 50: 482–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W. 1922. Evolutionary Naturalism. Chicago, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. 1980. ‘Justification, Discovery and the Naturalizing of Epistemology.’ Philosophy of Science, 47: 297321.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. 1984. ‘Empirical Psychology, Naturalized Epistemology, and First Philosophy.’ Philosophy of Science, 51: 667–76.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 2007 a. ‘Intuitions: Their Nature and Epistemic Efficacy.’ Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74: 5167.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 2007 b. ‘Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Intuition.’ Philosophical Studies, 132: 99107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinberg, J., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2001. ‘Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions.’ Philosophical Topics, 29: 429–60.Google Scholar