Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-42gr6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T15:55:55.432Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An Attempt To Defend Theism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

W. D. Hudson
Affiliation:
University of Exeter.

Abstract

The fact of evil has worried theists for a long time. The earliest clear statement of this worry is perhaps to be found in the book of Habbakuk: ‘Thou art of purer eyes than to behold evil, and canst not look on iniquity: wherefore lookest thou upon them that deal treacherously, and holdest thy tongue when the wicked devoureth the man that is more righteous than he?’ (i, 13). More precisely formulated, it comes to this: if God is good and omnipotent, why evil ? From his goodness it would follow necessarily that he does not will evil and from his omnipotence that he could prevent it; why then should it occur? Theists have attempted to escape from this dilemma by means of an argument which turns on the claim that human beings are, to some degree at any rate, free to choose and act as they will. They are free to do good or evil; frequently they choose the latter and that is why evils, or at least many of them, occur. This human freedom, however, is a necessary condition of personality and, as such, a great good; so it is perfectly consistent with the goodness of God that he should will it. But what of his omnipotence? The point of the argument is that God has to allow those evils which result from men making evil choices, and this certainlylooks, at first blush, like a limitation of his power. But, we are assured,it is not really a limitation because all it amounts to is that God cannot do the logically impossible, viz., make beings who, at one and the same time, are both free to do what they will and pre-determined to do good.To deny that God can do the logically impossible, of course, is not to den his omnipotence; it is merely to point out that there are some things which it would not make sense to say that he had done.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1964

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 18 note 1 See Flew, A. G. N. ‘Divine Omnipotence and Human Freedom’ in New Essays in Philosophical Theology (London, 1955)Google Scholar and Mackie, J. L., ‘Evil and Omnipotence’, Mind 1955.Google Scholar

page 20 note 1 See Flew, , op. cit. pp. 163-4.Google Scholar

page 21 note 1 In Prospect for Metaphysics ed. Ramsey, I. T. (London, 1961).Google Scholar

page 21 note 2 Op. cit. p. 127.Google Scholar

page 21 note 3 Ibid..

page 21 note 4 Op. cit. p. 128, italics mine.Google Scholar

page 22 note 1 Op. cit. p. 133.Google Scholar

page 23 note 1 Berdyaev, N., The Destiny of Man, p. 32.Google Scholar

page 24 note 1 Op. cit. p. 34.Google Scholar

page 24 note 2 Ibid..

page 25 note 1 ‘Can God's Existence be Disproved?’ in New Essays in Philosophical Theology (ed. Flew and Macintyre) p. 52.Google Scholar

page 25 note 2 Op. cit. p. 54.Google Scholar

page 26 note 1 Hume, D., Dialogues concerning Natural Religion, pt. IX.Google Scholar

page 26 note 2 Op. cit. p. 55.Google Scholar

page 26 note 3 Op. cit. p. 49.Google Scholar

page 27 note 1 Op. cit. p. 54.Google Scholar

page 27 note 2 See Wisdom, J., ‘Gods’ in Logic and Language, First series (ed.Flew, ) (Oxford, 1955);Google Scholar and Flew, A., ‘Theology and Falsification’ in New Essays in Philosophical Theology.Google Scholar

page 28 note 1 Op. cit. p. 54.