Skip to main content
Log in

Evilism, moral rationalism, and reasons internalism

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I show that the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent, and essentially omnimalevolent being is impossible given only two metaethical assumptions (viz., moral rationalism and reasons internalism). I then argue (pace Stephen Law) that such an impossibility undercuts Law’s (Relig Stud 46(3):353–373, 2010) evil god challenge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I say more about this idea in “Evilism” section below.

  2. Law (2010, p. 356).

  3. Morriston (2004, p. 87).

  4. Millican (1989, p. 196) emphasis in the original.

  5. Stein (1990, p. 163) uses the term ‘demon’ to denote an “omnimalevolent supernatural being”, but includes no serious discussion of what omnimalevolence amounts to. Likewise, both Cahn (1977), and Martin (1985) fail to reflect with great care on what omnimalevolence is.

  6. Forrest (2012, p. 37) stated:

    “The anti-God that I take seriously is the malicious omnipotent omniscient being, who, it is said, creates so that creatures will suffer, because of the joy this suffering gives It. This may be contrasted with a different idea of anti-God, that of an evil being that seeks to destroy things of value out of hatred or envy. An omni-potent omniscient being would not be envious. Moreover, destructive hatred cannot motivate creation. For these two reasons I find that rather implausible. My case holds, however, against that sort of anti-God as well as the malicious one. The variety of anti-Gods alerts us to the problem of positing any character to God, whether benign, indifferent, or malicious. There are many such character traits we could hypothesize. Why not a God who creates as a jest? Or a God who loves drama? Or a God who, adapting Haldane’s quip, is fond of beetles? Or, more seriously, a God who just loves creating regardless of the joy or suffering of creatures?”

  7. Forrest (2012, p. 37).

  8. Ibid.

  9. I need the above metaphysical assumption for otherwise I’m open to the objection that I’ve under-described the situation. Thanks to Andy Egan here. I should add that I am not assuming possibilism by denying the existence of haecceitic properties. There are ways of doing quantified modal logic without demanding that such a logic be about incommunicable properties.

  10. This principle is similar to what David Enoch calls “crazily strong” judgment internalism (Enoch 2011, p. 249), though see his comments about Plato’s brand of internalism in (Ibid., p. 250). It seems that Daniels and Enoch disagree about what kind of internalism Plato affirmed.

  11. On this idea see Broad (1940, pp. 128–130); cf. the discussion in Coady (1997, pp. 393–397). There is an interesting discussion of conscientious acts and egoism in Shafer-Landau (2012, p. 94).

  12. One could put moral cognitivism in terms of beliefs. For example, one could say that moral cognitivism is the view that (to quote Michael Smith) “moral judgements...express beliefs about the way the world is morally...” Smith (2005, p. 4).

  13. Swinburne wrote, “[f]urther, if one takes a certain view about the status of moral judgements, God’s perfect goodness follows deductively from his omniscience and his perfect freedom.” Swinburne (2004, p. 99).

  14. Swinburne (2004, p. 101).

  15. ibid. The above suggests that Swinburne also needs the view that moral principles can serve as reasons for action. For more on this kind of assumption see my discussion of moral rationalism below.

  16. Swinburne (2004, p. 101).

  17. Law makes a point like this one as well, though Law does not have Swinburne in mind (see Law 2010, p. 371).

  18. Law 2010, p. 371.

  19. Shafer-Landau (2003, p. 190), though he says the view also suggests that moral facts strictly imply “reasons for belief” as well (Ibid., 206); cf. Donagan (1977), Gewirth (1978); Harman (1975, pp. 4–11, 1984, pp. 34–41) with Brink (1989, p. 52) reading Harman (1975, 1984) in a way that suggests he is committed to moral rationalism; Parfit (2011a, p. 38, and pp. 141–149), Smith (1994); and see the criticism of moral rationalism in Timmons (1999, pp. 247–252).

  20. Smith (1994, pp. 64–65).

  21. Cf. Parfit (2011b, p. 441).

  22. Shafer-Landau (2003, p. 204 emphasis in the original). There is also a view which says that normative truths are rule-implying or rule-entailing. The view recommends that normative truths imply rules which inform moral agents about what is incorrect or correct. See on this idea Parfit (2011a, p. 144). I’m not suggesting that Parfit endorses the view that normative truths are rule-implying, he merely discusses the view.

    Darwall (2006, p. 286) hints at a hybrid position which suggests that the reason why duties are practical reason-implying is due to both the duties themselves, and some external factor or factors.

  23. Paraphrasing Smith (1994, p. 61), but see also Blackburn (1984, pp. 187–189). There’s an interesting criticism of Smith’s work on normative reasons and the like in Wedgwood (2007, pp. 76–79).

  24. Smith’s wording from Smith (1994, p. 130).

  25. Smith (1994, p. 177).

  26. Discussed by Brink (1989, pp. 45–46).

  27. Discussed by Darwall (1995, pp. 10–11) and Enoch (2011, pp. 249–250).

  28. Discussed by Shafer-Landau (2003, pp. 165–189).

  29. Discussed by Enoch (2011, pp. 247–259).

  30. Discussed in ibid., 259–266.

  31. See the nice discussion of most of these internalisms in Enoch (2011, pp. 247–266).

  32. Someone who determines that some action is right, but is simply indifferent about that action, motivation-wise.

  33. This is Enoch’s (2011, p. 250) objection to “really strong judgment-internalism”. Brink (1989, p. 45) has a different worry about a similar kind of internalism as well.

  34. I will call this principle modest internalism. This is similar to Darwall’s (2006, p. 286) understanding of existence internalism. See also Korsgaard (1986), and Williams (1981).

    I’m assuming that C* does not include a world index.

    The above idea of reasons internalism follows Shafer-Landau’s portrayal of the thesis in Shafer-Landau (2003, p. 170).

  35. Darwall (2006).

  36. Darwall (2006, p. 284, p. 287); cf. Wood (2008, p. 22).

  37. Darwall (2006, p. 286).

  38. That Kant goes in for rationalism and some kind of internalism is admitted also by Brink (1989, p. 50). Also, Thomas Nagel (1970) seems to defend versions of the kind of Kantian doctrines I discuss above.

  39. \(Q.v\). note 23.

  40. Smith (1994, pp. 156–159).

  41. See, for example, Dreier (1992, p. 15 noting that most philosophers, “who have thought about the matter” would agree with him), and Fine (2002, p. 270) also cites in this vein, Klagge (1984, p. 378), McFetridge (1985, pp. 251–252), Shoemaker (1987, p. 441), and Zangwill (1995). I can add Swinburne (2003, p. 320 for at least moral truths like “all acts of feeding the starving are good” (ibid.). Elsewhere he states, “[t]he fundamental moral truths are necessary truths.” 2013, p. 180); and two divine command theorists Craig (2008, p. 178) and Murphy (2011).

    Since I invoked Kantianism for the purposes of motivating moral rationalism and modest (reasons) internalism, I should point out that it was precisely because Kant deemed moral principles to be necessary truths that he rejected divine command theories that depict God as the author of the moral law. He wrote,

    “The one who declares that a law, which is in accord with his will, obligates another, he gives [legislates] a law. The legislator is not simultaneously an author of the law, only when the law is contingent. When the laws are necessarily practical and he only declares that they are in accord with his will, he is the legislator. Thus no one, including God is the author of the moral laws, since they do not spring from the will [choice], but are practically necessary. Were they not necessary, it would be possible that lying be a virtue. The moral laws can only stand under a legislator; it can be a being that has the power and authority to execute the laws and to declare that the moral law is simultaneously a law of his will, and obligate everyone to act in accordance. Thus, this being is a legislator, but not author. Precisely as God is not the author of the fact that triangles have three angles...” As quoted and translated by Kain (1999).

  42. McMahan (2002, p. 189). I actually believe that the above impossibility argument fares better than the one I lodged against the type of evilism Law seemed to have in mind. This is because the argument I am now running requires as its key premise a truth I consider to be more obvious than either moral rationalism or reasons internalism (\(i.e\)., \(p)\).

  43. The response is admittedly Moorean. If this bothers you, one could add to the above impossibility argument one’s favorite response to skepticism.

  44. Notice that this brand of evilism still has need of (as a necessary condition) the existence of an evil god. It’s just that evilism is now, at best, a contingent thesis.

  45. It is clear that Law has in mind logical possibility. He says (Law 2010, p. 371):

    “[w]hat we have established, perhaps, is that there are certain logical limits on God’s evilness...just as there are logical limits on His power...Evil god can still be maximally evil—as evil as it is logically possible to be.”

  46. Rumfitt (2010, p. 46. n. 11).

  47. I’m quoting the syllogistic presentation of the argument in Schellenberg (1993, p. 83). I’ve left out the explanatory points Schellenberg has between each line of the argument. Cf.Schellenberg (2004).

  48. Schellenberg’s (1993, p. 83).

  49. Schellenberg (1993, p. 83).

  50. Ibid.

  51. Ibid.

  52. An instance of \(\Box \,(\hbox {p}\supset \hbox {q})\supset \Box \,({\sim } \hbox {q} \supset {\sim } \hbox {p}\)).

  53. Schellenberg’s (1993, p. 83).

  54. Ibid. by reiteration of (3).

  55. I’m paraphrasing Rowe (2004, p. 5).

  56. See Law (2010, p. 354).

  57. The problem of good is roughly the idea that the existence of particular goods in the world show that an EG does not exist. See Law’s discussion of the argument from good in (Law 2010, p. 356).

  58. Millican (1989, p. 207).

  59. And so Law (2010, p. 372) states:

    “The point is this: even supposing an evil god is, for some reason X, an impossibility, we can still ask the hypothetical question: setting aside the fact that so-and-so establishes that an evil god is an impossibility, how reasonable would it otherwise be to suppose that such an evil being exists? If the answer is ‘highly unreasonable’, i.e. because of the problem of good, then the evil-god challenge can still be run. We can still ask theists to explain why, if they would otherwise reject the evil-god hypothesis as highly unreasonable, do they not take the same view regarding the good-god hypothesis?”

    Morriston (2004, p. 88 emphasis in the original) stated:

    “...many theists would claim that demonism is logically incoherent...I think [this] is a mistake...but I won’t insist on that point here. Even if demonism is incoherent in just the way that some theists believe, I think it is still useful to ask whether there is any other way to show that demonism is false. Specifically, I want to ask whether there is some range of facts about our world, relative to which demonism is sufficiently unlikely to warrant the judgment that the Demon does not exist.”

  60. Law (2010, p. 372).

  61. Since for any \(p\) and \(q\), \(\Box \, (\Box \sim \hbox {p}\supset \Box \, (\hbox {p} \supset \hbox {q}\))). And of course, \(q\) can be a contradiction.

  62. I am assuming that the strength of ampliative inference is reducible to something more primitive (something describable by the deliverances of the probability calculus). I do not actually believe this is the case, but because this is often assumed in the philosophy of religion literature I assume it in the above discussion.

  63. Williamson (2000, p. 214).

  64. I’m paraphrasing the thought of Rowe (2004, p. 5), but reversing the content.

  65. Parfit (2011a, p. 141).

  66. Cf. Sider (2010, p. 203).

References

  • Blackburn, S. (1984). Spreading the word. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. O. (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1940). Conscience and conscientious action. Philosophy (The Journal of the British Institute of Philosophy), 15(58), 115–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cahn, S. (1977). Cacodaemony. Analysis, 37(2), 69–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coady, C. A. J. (1997). Objecting morally. The Journal of Ethics, 1(4), 375–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. L. (2008). Reasonable faith: Christian truth and apologetics (3rd ed.). Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, C. B. (1997). God, demon, good, evil. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 31(2), 177–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (1995). The british moralists and the internal “ought”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2006). Morality and practical reason: A Kantian approach. In D. Copp (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of ethical theory (pp. 282–320). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donagan, A. (1977). The theory of morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (1992). The supervenience argument against moral realism. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 30(3), 13–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2011). Taking morality seriously: A defense of robust realism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2002). The varieties of necessity. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 253–281). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2007). Developmental theism: From pure will to unbounded love. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2012). Replying to the anti-god challenge: A god without moral character acts well. Religious Studies, 48(1), 35–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth, A. (1978). Reason and morality. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1952). The language of morals. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1975). Moral relativism defended. The Philosophical Review, 84(1), 3–22.

  • Harman, G. (1984). Is there a Single True Morality?. In D. Copp & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Morality, reason, and truth: New essays on the foundations of ethics (pp. 27–48). Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.

  • Kain, P. (1999). Kant’s moral constructivism and his conception of legislation. The Paideia Project Online http://www.bu.edu/wep/Papers/TEth/TEthKain.htm.

  • Kant, I. (1996a). Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals. In Practical philosophy (trans. and edited by Gregor, M. J., introduced by Wood, A.) (pp. 37–108). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (1996b). Metaphysics of morals. In Practical philosophy (trans. and edited by Gregor, M. J, introduced by Wood, A.) (pp. 353–604). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Klagge, J. C. (1984). An alleged difficulty concerning moral properties. Mind, 93(371), 370–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1986). Skepticism about practical reason. The Journal of Philosophy, 83, 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Law, S. (2010). The evil-god challenge. Religious Studies, 46(3), 353–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1985). The coherence of the hypothesis of an omnipotent, omniscient, free and perfectly evil being. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 17(3), 185–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McFetridge, I. G. (1985). Supervenience, realism, necessity. The Philosophical Quarterly, 35(140), 245–258.

  • McMahan, J. (2002). The ethics of killing: Problems at the margins of life. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. J. R. (1989). The devil’s advocate. Cogito, 3(3), 193–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morriston, W. (2004). The evidential argument from goodness. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 42, 87–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M. C. (2011). God and moral law: On the theistic explanation of morality. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1970). The possibility of altruism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011a). On what matters (Vol. 1). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011b). On what matters (Vol. 2). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. (2004). Evil is evidence against theistic belief. In M. L. Peterson & R. J. VanArragon (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of religion (contemporary debates in philosophy) (pp. 3–13). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumfitt, I. (2010). Logical necessity. In B. Hale & A. Hoffmann (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 35–64). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. L. (1993). Divine hiddenness and human reason (cornell studies in philosophy of religion) ithaca. NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. L. (2004). Divine hiddenness Justifies Atheism. In M. L. Peterson & R. J. VanArragon (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of religion (contemporary debates in philosophy) (pp. 30–41). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A defence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2012). The fundamentals of ethics (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1987). Review of: ‘Spreading the Word’. By Simon Blackburn. Noûs, 21(3), 438–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2010). Logic for philosophy New York. NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1987). The humean theory of motivation. Mind, 96(381), 36–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2005). Meta-ethics. In F. Jackson & M. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy (pp. 3–30). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. (1990). God, the demon, and the status of theodicies. American Philosophical Quarterly, 27(2), 163–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2003). Morality and god. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 225(3), 315–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2004). The existence of God (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2013). Mind, grain, & free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timmons, M. (1999). Morality without foundations: A defence of ethical contextualism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2007). The nature of normativity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Moral luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (2008). Kantian ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (1995). Moral supervenience. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 20(1), 240–262.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Andy Egan, Blake Giunta, Alexander R. Pruss, Joshua Rasmussen, and Dean Zimmerman for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher Gregory Weaver.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Weaver, C.G. Evilism, moral rationalism, and reasons internalism. Int J Philos Relig 77, 3–24 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-014-9472-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-014-9472-3

Keywords

Navigation