Skip to main content
Log in

Credence for conclusions: a brief for Jeffrey’s rule

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Some arguments are good; others are not. How can we tell the difference? This article advances three proposals as a partial answer to this question. The proposals are keyed to arguments conditioned by different degrees of uncertainty: mild, where the argument’s premises are hedged with point-valued probabilities; moderate, where the premises are hedged with interval probabilities; and severe, where the premises are hedged with non-numeric plausibilities such as ‘very likely’ or ‘unconfirmed’. For mild uncertainty, the article proposes to apply a principle referred to as ‘Jeffrey’s rule’, for the principle is a generalization of Jeffrey conditionalization. For moderate uncertainty, the proposal is to extend Jeffrey’s rule for use with probability intervals. For severe uncertainty, the article proposes that even when lack of probabilistic information prevents the application of Jeffrey’s rule, the rule can be adapted to these conditions with the aid of a suitable plausibility measure. Together, the three proposals introduce an approach to argument evaluation that complements established frameworks for evaluating arguments: deductive soundness, informal logic, argumentation schemes, pragma-dialectics, and Bayesian inference. Nevertheless, this approach can be looked at as a generalization of the truth and validity conditions of the classical criterion for sound argumentation

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Skyrms writes of statements rather than propositions, perhaps to avoid the Platonic realism often associated with propositions. I will use the term ‘statement’ throughout this paper to mean that which is asserted by a sentence. Some of the ontological questions raised by propositions and statements can be sampled in a classic exchange between Cartwright (1962, 1968) and Stroll (1967).

  2. This and the following paragraph are responses to highly constructive comments by an anonymous reviewer.

  3. Plausibilities are discussed in Sects. 4 and 5 below.

  4. Inductive cogency is actually a generalization of deductive soundness. Deductive validity is a limiting case of inductive strength, and the truth requirement is the same in both criteria (Welch 2014, pp. 26–28).

  5. According to this rule, a conclusion of the form ‘Possibly A’ is less probative than one of the form ‘Actually A’, which is in turn less probative than one of the form ‘Necessarily A’.

  6. I am indebted to Geoff Goddu for spotting a difficulty with an earlier version of this argument.

  7. Probability intervals have been objects of study at least as far back as Keynes: “Many probabilities, which are incapable of numerical measurement, can be placed nevertheless between numerical limits” (1921, p. 160, Keynes’ emphasis). On the extent to which Keynes did or should have rejected Ramsey’s influential critique of his theory, see Runde (1994).

  8. Like Pfeifer and Kleiter, Douven and Verbrugge (2013) endorse the thesis of conditional probability and offer empirical results in support.

  9. Bradley’s (2009, pp. 240–241) complementary analysis identifies four sources of these failures: unawareness of existing prospects, consciously imposed limits on deliberation (suspension of judgment, for example), lack of relevant information, and unresolved conflict. Unresolved conflict coincides with Levi’s sense of indeterminacy.

  10. “[A]ll [elicitation] subjects report, or otherwise reveal, that they do not know their own preferences; they experience wavering and indecision that cannot be identified with mere indifference” (Savage 1971, p. 795).

  11. Though these systems have difficulties with argument by analogy, the difficulties can be addressed in relatively straightforward fashion (Kuipers 1984; Welch 1999).

  12. This rule can be seen as a generalization of a maximum probability rule for conjunctions proposed by Hahn et al. (2013, p. 23).

  13. The descriptions of non-probabilistic approaches are based on Halpern (2003, ch. 2), but they adapt Halpern’s set-theoretic formulations to the idiom of statements employed throughout this paper.

References

  • Adams, E. W. (1975). The logic of conditionals: An application of probability to deductive logic. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, E. W. (1998). A primer of probability logic. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, F. J., & Aumann, R. J. (1963). A definition of subjective probability. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics,34(1), 199–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J., & Bonelli, M. (2013). Syllogistic in the anon Heiberg. In J. Barnes (Ed.), Logical matters: Essays in ancient philosophy II (pp. 683–728). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Betz, G. (2013). In defence of the value free ideal. European Journal for Philosophy of Science,3(2), 207–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J. A. (2007). Relevance, acceptability, and sufficiency today. Anthropology and Philosophy,8(1–2), 33–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J. A., & Johnson, R. H. (1993). Logical self-defense (3rd ed.). Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R. (2009). Revising incomplete attitudes. Synthese,171(2), 235–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1952). The continuum of inductive methods. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1971). Inductive logic and rational decisions, A basic system of inductive logic, part 1. In R. Carnap & R. C. Jeffrey (Eds.), Studies in inductive logic and probability (Vol. I, pp. 5–31, 33–165). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1980). A basic system of inductive logic, part 2. In R. C. Jeffrey (Ed.), Studies in inductive logic and probability (Vol. II, pp. 7–155). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, R. L. (1962). Propositions. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytical philosophy, first series (pp. 81–103). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, R. L. (1968). Propositions again. Noûs,2(3), 229–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chu, F. C., & Halpern, J. Y. (2004). Great expectations. Part II: Generalized expected utility as a universal decision rule. Artificial Intelligence,159(1–2), 207–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chu, F. C., & Halpern, J. Y. (2008). Great expectations. Part I: On the customizability of generalized expected utility. Theory and Decision,64(1), 1–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1937). La prévision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives. Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré, 7(1), 1–68. English edition: De Finetti, B. (1980). Foresight: Its logical laws, its subjective sources. In H. E. Kyburg & H. E. Smokler (Eds.), Studies in subjective probability (pp. 53–118). New York: R. E. Krieger.

  • Dempster, A. P. (1967). Upper and lower probabilities induced by a multivalued mapping. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics,38(2), 325–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., & Verbrugge, S. (2013). The probabilities of conditionals revisited. Cognitive Science,37(4), 711–730.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubois, D., & Prade, H. (1980). Fuzzy sets and systems: Theory and applications. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubois, D., & Prade, H. (1988). Possibility theory. New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics,75(4), 643–669.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogelin, R. J., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2010). Understanding arguments: An introduction to informal logic (8th ed.). Belmont, CA: Thomson Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, N., & Halpern, J. Y. (1995). Plausibility measures: A user’s guide. In Proceedings of the eleventh conference on uncertainty in artificial intelligence (UAI’95) (pp. 175–184). https://dslpitt.org/uai/papers/95/p175-friedman.pdf. Accessed 3 April 2018.

  • Godden, D., & Zenker, F. (2018). A probabilistic analysis of argument cogency. Synthese,195(4), 1715–1740.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Hornikx, J. (2016). A normative framework for argument quality: Argumentation schemes with a Bayesian foundation. Synthese,193(6), 1833–1873.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2006a). A normative theory of argument strength. Informal Logic,26(1), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2006b). A Bayesian approach to informal argument fallacies. Synthese,152(2), 207–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., Oaksford, M., & Harris, A. J. L. (2013). Testimony and argument: A Bayesian perspective”. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation: The practical side of probability (pp. 15–38). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J. Y. (2003). Reasoning about uncertainty. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1966). A two-dimensional continuum of inductive methods. In J. Hintikka & P. Suppes (Eds.), Aspects of inductive logic (pp. 113–132). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., & Niiniluoto, I. (1976). An axiomatic foundation for the logic of inductive generalization. In M. Przełęcki, K. Szaniawski, & R. Wójcicki (Eds.), Formal methods in the methodology of empirical sciences (pp. 57–81). Dordrecht: D. Reidel (Wrocław: Ossolineum).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1983). The logic of decision (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. M. (2010). A defense of imprecise credences in inference and decision making. Philosophical Perspectives,24(1), 281–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. M. (1921). A treatise on probability. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korb, K. (2003). Bayesian informal logic and fallacy. Informal Logic,24(1), 41–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. F. (1984). Two types of inductive analogy by similarity. Erkenntnis,21(1), 63–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1985). Imprecision and indeterminacy in probability judgment. Philosophy of Science,52(3), 390–409.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. The Philosophical Review,85(3), 297–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1998). Theoretical (epistemic) virtues. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, A. (2017). Vague credence. Synthese,194(10), 3931–3954.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, N. (2013). On argument strength. In Frank Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation: The practical side of probability (pp. 185–193). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2006). Inference in conditional probability logic. Kybernetika,42(4), 391–404.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2007). Human reasoning with imprecise probabilities: Modus ponens and denying the antecedent. In 5th International symposium on imprecise probability: Theories and applications. http://www.sipta.org/isipta07/proceedings/papers/s050.pdf. Accessed 3 April 2018.

  • Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2009). Framing human inference by coherence based probability logic. Journal of Applied Logic,7(2), 206–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (2003). Cognitive carpentry: A blueprint for how to build a person. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V., & Ullian, J. S. (1978). The web of belief (2nd ed.). New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1931). Truth and probability. In R. B. Braithwaite (Ed.), The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays (pp. 156–198). New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1979). Cognitive systematization: A systems-theoretic approach to a coherentist theory of knowledge. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Runde, J. (1994). Keynes after Ramsey: In defence of A treatise of probability. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science,25(1), 97–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. J. (1971). Elicitation of personal probabilities and expectations. Journal of the American Statistical Association,66(4), 783–801.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarry, E. (2016). Naming thy name: Cross talk in Shakespeare’s sonnets. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica,57(3), 571–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, G. (1976). A mathematical theory of evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, G. (1987). Belief functions and possibility measures. In J. C. Bezdek (Ed.), Analysis of fuzzy information (Vol. I, pp. 51–84). Boca Raton: CRC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2000). Choice and chance: An introduction to inductive logic (4th ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1988). Ordinal conditional functions: A dynamic theory of epistemic states. In W. L. Harper & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Causation in decision, belief change, and statistics (Vol. II, pp. 105–134). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1990). A general non-probabilistic theory of inductive reasoning. In R. D. Shachter, T. S. Levitt, J. Lemmer, & L. N. Kanal (Eds.), Uncertainty in artificial intelligence (Vol. 4, pp. 149–158). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief: Ranking theory and its philosophical applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroll, A. (1967). Statements. In A. Stroll (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays in the theory of knowledge (pp. 179–203). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, S. (2008). Reason and the grain of belief. Noûs,42(1), 139–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1992). Argumentation, communication, and fallacies: A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walley, P. (1991). Statistical reasoning with imprecise probabilities. London: Chapman and Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walley, P. (2000). Towards a unified theory of imprecise probability. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning,24(2–3), 125–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1996). Argumentation schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (2005). Justification of argumentation schemes. The Australasian Journal of Logic,3, 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (2007). Evaluating practical reasoning. Synthese,157(2), 197–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., Reed, C., & Macagno, F. (2008). Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welch, J. R. (1999). Singular analogy and quantitative inductive logics. Theoria,14(2), 207–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welch, J. R. (2014). Moral strata: Another approach to reflective equilibrium. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh, L. (1978). Fuzzy sets as a basis for a theory of possibility. Fuzzy Sets and Systems,1(1), 3–28.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper grew out of a presentation at the Eleventh Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation, University of Windsor, Canada, on May 19, 2016. I am grateful to the organizers for the invitation, and to the participants, particularly Frank Zenker, David Godden, and Geoff Goddu, for stimulating exchanges. I am also indebted to two anonymous reviewers for this journal, whose comments were invaluable in the maturation of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John R. Welch.

Appendix

Appendix

This appendix includes the details of three probabilistic calculations referred to in the body of the paper. The first and third calculations rely on Jeffrey’s rule; the second uses Bayes’ theorem. For easy reference, the relevant theorem is restated for each calculation.

  1. 1.

    point-valued \( p(A \to B) \) in Sect. 2

Consider the argument A, therefore \( A \to B \) . Truth-table analyses show that there are logical grounds for the following probabilities:

$$ \begin{array}{l} p\left(E \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, 1/2 \\ p\left({H|E} \right) \, = p(A \to B|A) \, = \, 1/2 \\ p(H|\overline{E} ) = p(A \to B|\overline{A} ) \, = \, 1. \end{array} $$

To determine the epistemic probability of the conclusion \( A \to B \), we can apply Jeffrey’s rule:

$$\begin{aligned} p\left(H \right) &= p\left(E \right)p\left({H|E} \right) + p(\overline{E} )p(H|\overline{E}) \\ p(A \to B) &= p\left(A \right)p(A \to B|A) + p(\overline{A} )p(A \to B|\overline{A} )\\ &= \left( {1/2 \, \times \, 1/2} \right) + \left( {1/2 \, \times \, 1} \right)\\ &= 3/4 \end{aligned}$$
  1. 2.

    point-valued \( p(A \to B|A) \) in Sect. 2

Once again, the argument is A, therefore \( A \to B \). Truth-table analyses can verify that there are logical grounds for these probabilities:

$$ \begin{array}{l} p\left(H \right) \, = p(A \to B) \, = \, 3/4 \\ p\left({E|H} \right) \, = p(A|A \to B) \, = \, 1/3 \\ p(E|\overline{H} )\, = p(A|{-}(A \to B)) \, = \, 1. \end{array} $$

Then Bayes’ theorem can be used to calculate the inductive probability of the conclusion \( A \to B \) given the premise A:

$$ p\left({H |E} \right) = \frac{p\left(H \right)\,p(E|H) }{{p\left(H \right)p(E|H) + p\left({\overline{H} } \right)p(E|\overline{H} )}} $$
$$ \begin{aligned} p\left({A \to B|A} \right) &= \frac{{p\left({A \to B} \right)\,p(A|A \to B) }}{{p\left({A \to B} \right)p\left({A |A \to B} \right) + p\left({{-}\left( {A \to B} \right)} \right)p(A|{-}\left( {A \to B} \right))}} \\ &= \frac{3/4 \times 1/3 }{{\left( {3/4 \times 1/3} \right) + \left( {1/4 \times 1} \right)}} \\ &= 1/2 \end{aligned} $$
  1. 3.

    interval-valued p(A) in Sect. 3

Here the argument is \( A \to B \), B, therefore A. Suppose that there are empirical grounds for the following probabilistic intervals:

$$ \begin{array}{l} p\left(E \right) \, = p((A \to B) \wedge B) \, = \, .6 \, {-} \, .7 \\ p\left({H|E} \right) \, = p(A|(A \to B) \wedge B) \, = \, .5 \, {-} \, .6 \\ p(H|\overline{E} ) \, = p(A|{-}((A \to B) \wedge B)) \, = \, .4 \, {-} \, .5. \end{array} $$

We want to determine the epistemic probability of the conclusion A. Hence we consider the possible combinations of minimum (min) and maximum (MAX) values of these probabilities in the light of Jeffrey’s rule: \( p\left(H \right) = p\left(E \right)p\left({H|E} \right) + p(\overline{E} )p(H|\overline{E} ) \):

$$ \begin{array}{l} \hbox{min}\,p\left(E \right), \, \hbox{min}\, p\left({H|E} \right), \, \hbox{min}\, p(H|\overline{E} ):p\left(H \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, \left( {.6 \, \times \, .5} \right) \, + \, \left( {.4 \, \times \, .4} \right) \, = \, .46 \\ \hbox{min}\,p\left(E \right), \, \hbox{min}\,p\left({H|E} \right),{\text{ MAX}}\,p(H|\overline{E} ):p\left(H \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, \left( {.6 \, \times \, .5} \right) \, + \, \left( {.4 \, \times .5} \right) \, = \, .50 \\ \hbox{min}\,p\left(E \right),{\text{ MAX}}\,p\left({H|E} \right), \, \hbox{min}\,p(H|\overline{E} ):p\left(H \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, \left( {.6 \, \times \, .6} \right) \, + \, \left( {.4 \, \times \, .4} \right) \, = \, .52 \\ \hbox{min}\,p\left(E \right),{\text{ MAX}}\,p\left({H|E} \right),{\text{ MAX}}\,p(H|\overline{E} ):p\left(H \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, \left( {.6 \, \times \, .6} \right) \, + \, \left( {.4 \, \times \, .5} \right) \, = \, .56 \\ {\text{MAX}}p\left(E \right), \, \hbox{min}\,p\left({H|E} \right), \, \hbox{min}\,p(H|\overline{E} ):p\left(H \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, \left( {.7 \, \times \, .5} \right) \, + \, \left( {.3 \, \times \, .4} \right) \, = \, .47 \\ {\text{MAX}}p\left(E \right), \, \hbox{min}\,p\left({H|E} \right),{\text{ MAX}}\,p(H|\overline{E} ):p\left(H \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, \left( {.7 \, \times \, .5} \right) \, + \, \left( {.3 \, \times \, .5} \right) \, = \, .50 \\ {\text{MAX}}p\left(E \right),{\text{ MAX}}\,p\left({H|E} \right),\hbox{min}\,p(H|\overline{E} ):p\left(H \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, \left( {.7 \, \times \, .6} \right) \, + \, \left( {.3 \, \times \, .4} \right) \, = \, .54 \\ {\text{MAX}}p\left(E \right),{\text{ MAX}}\,p\left({H|E} \right),{\text{ MAX}}\,p(H|\overline{E} ):p\left(H \right) \, = p\left(A \right) \, = \, \left( {.7 \, \times \, .6} \right) \, + \, \left( {.3 \, \times \, .5} \right) \, = \, .57. \end{array} $$

Since the lowest of these values is .46 and the highest is .57, the epistemic probability of A is the interval .46–.57.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Welch, J.R. Credence for conclusions: a brief for Jeffrey’s rule. Synthese 197, 2051–2072 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1782-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1782-z

Keywords

Navigation