Skip to main content
Log in

Other People’s Problems: Student Distancing, Epistemic Responsibility, and Injustice

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In classes that examine entrenched injustices like sexism or racism, students sometimes use “distancing strategies” to dissociate themselves from the injustice being studied. Education researchers argue that distancing is a mechanism through which students, especially students of apparent privilege, deny their complicity in systemic injustice. While I am sympathetic to this analysis, I argue that there is much at stake in student distancing that the current literature fails to recognize. On my view, distancing perpetuates socially sanctioned forms of ignorance and unknowing, through which students misrecognize not only their complicity in injustice, but also the ways that injustice shapes the world, their lives, and their knowledge. Thus, distancing is pedagogically problematic because it prevents students from understanding important social facts, and because it prevents them from engaging with perspectives, analyses, and testimonies that might beneficially challenge their settled views and epistemic habits. To substantiate this new analysis, I draw on recent work on epistemologies of ignorance, especially José Medina’s account of “active ignorance.” In order to respond to student distancing, I argue, it is not sufficient for teachers to make students aware of injustice, or of their potential complicity in it. Beyond this, teachers should cultivate epistemic virtue in the classroom and encourage students to take responsibility for better ways of knowing. The article ends by outlining several classroom practices for beginning this work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This phrasing, and the title of this article, are inspired by Lisa Delpit’s Other People’s Children (2006).

  2. For a full critique of discourses of ‘color-blindness’, see Bonilla-Silva (2006). For pedagogical approaches that challenge these discourses, see Thompson (1997), Applebaum (2010), Blackwell (2010), and Teel (2014).

  3. For examples of these discourses, see Alice McIntyre (1997) on “white talk,” George Yancy (2008) on “whitely-being-in-the-world,” and Shannon Sullivan (2014) on whiteness as etiquette.

  4. As I argue below, this does not necessarily excuse students for any moral, political, or epistemic fault they may incur through distancing.

  5. For overviews, see Mills (1997, pp. 17–19), Tuana (2006), and Tuana and Sullivan (2006). See also the essays collected in Sullivan and Tuana (2007) and Malewski and Jaramillo (2011).

  6. Miranda Fricker, whose work on epistemic injustice intersects with the epistemology of ignorance literature, calls this condition “testimonial injustice” (2007).

  7. Medina does not believe that this misrecognition is universally or exclusively associated with socially privileged subjects, and he is careful not to attribute an automatic epistemic lucidity to oppressed subjects (2013, pp. 30, 40–5, 74, 191).

  8. None of the researchers cited here claim or imply that distancing is only done by white students. But where they frame their analyses in Black-white binaries, they miss opportunities to address the distancing of non-white students. Moreover, they underemphasize the contextual and intersectional nature of privilege and epistemic impairment. Finally, they risk developing pedagogies that focus almost exclusively on challenging the ignorance of white students, with little to say about teaching students of color.

  9. I thank Stephen Bloch-Schulman for emphasizing this point.

  10. Medina’s remarks on meta-ignorance are especially apt for powerfully socializing contexts like academic departments and teacher training: “Meta-blindness protects first-order forms of blindness, which become recalcitrant and resistant to change and improvement because the recognition that there is anything that requires change or improvement is systemically blocked” (pp. 149–150).

  11. I draw on theories of epistemic responsibility that view epistemic agents as embedded in social relations characterized by difference, in order to explore context-specific epistemological obligations to others. Here, Code (1987) and Fricker (2007) are foundational, while Bevan (2011) is a more direct predecessor to parts of my argument. Important work on epistemic responsibility has also been framed in universalistic, deontological terms (e.g., Steup 1988; Nottelman 2007; Booth 2012; Elgin 2013; McHugh 2013), but this is less relevant for the present essay.

  12. The field of virtue epistemology is diverse. I draw on virtue responsibilism, which conceives epistemic virtues as actively exercised traits of persons, analogous to moral virtues, for which individuals can be held responsible (Code 1987; Montmarquet 1993). Most relevant to my arguments are efforts to connect virtue epistemology to educational practices, such Bevan (2011), Battaly (2013), and Baehr (2013).

  13. “The epistemic virtues are dispositions if not governing choice, at least affecting the will. They are dispositions to put forth appropriate effort. They are not dispositions to choose a belief. In short, they are active frames of mind, not unthinking habits” (Bevan 2011, p. 262).

  14. This insight of anti-racist theory goes back at least to W. E. B. Du Bois, and has recently been developed by Lugones and Spelman (1983), Collins (2008), Mills (2007), and others.

  15. However, as we know from Aristotle, virtues can become vices when practiced to excess, so reflective moderation is necessary here. I thank Jean Keller and her undergraduate students for pointing this out.

  16. More generally, Cahill and Bloch-Schulman (2012) emphasize that encouraging students to take responsibility for their own learning—and in particular, for practicing good epistemic habits—facilitates deep learning and self-authorship (pp. 56–57).

  17. Students give more credence and less resistance to teachers whose embodied comportment corresponds to their expectations of intellectual authority (Miller and Chamberlin 2000; Puchner and Roseboro 2011). In the U.S., this typically means white, male, presumed cisgendered and heterosexual, native English speakers, like myself. I hope the strategies discussed here will be helpful for other teachers, but I acknowledge that classroom practices are differently effective for different teachers and students.

  18. I thank the anonymous reviewer who urged me to incorporate the issue of meta-ignorance in this article.

  19. On the epistemic and pedagogical value of diversity more generally, see Robertson (2013).

  20. This is a classic problem of virtue development. See for instance Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics Book I. 3–4 (1999, pp. 2–4).

  21. There are many situations, especially in philosophy classes, when logical argument or public reason requires setting aside particular perspectives in favor of abstraction. In my classes, I help students determine for themselves when and why generalized “public reasons” are more appropriate than appeals to particular perspectives, and I help them use both kinds of reflection to deepen their thinking.

  22. I thank Stephen Bloch-Schulman, Jeff Edmonds, Jean Keller, and José Medina for pressing me to think further in these directions.

  23. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pushing me to expand the material in this paragraph.

  24. Shannon Sullivan’s analysis of “white trash” emphasizes how ‘respectable’ whites dissociate from lower-class, ‘disrespectable’ whites in ways that disadvantage the latter while enabling socio-economically privileged whites to distance themselves from racism (Sullivan 2014, pp. 23–58). See also Schroer (2007).

References

  • Ahmed, Sara. 2004. Declarations of whiteness: The non-performativity of anti-racism. Borderlands e-journal 3.2. www.borderlands.net.au/vol3no2_2004/ahmed_declarations.htm. Accessed 28 April 2015.

  • Applebaum, Barbara. 2010. Being white, being good: White complicity, white moral responsibility, and social justice pedagogy. New York: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Applebaum, Barbara. 2012. Reframing responsibility in the social justice classroom. Race Ethnicity and Education 15(5): 615–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Applebaum, Barbara. 2013. Vigilance as a response to white complicity. Educational Theory 63(1): 17–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1999. Nichomachean ethics, trans. Terence Irwin. Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Baehr, Jason. 2013. Educating for intellectual virtues: From theory to practice. Journal of Philosophy of Education 47(2): 248–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailey, Alison. 2007. Strategic ignorance. In Race and epistemologies of ignorance, ed. Shannon Sullivan, and Nancy Tuana, 77–94. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battaly, Heather. 2013. Detecting epistemic vice in higher education policy: Epistemic insensitivity in the seven solutions and the REF. Journal of Philosophy of Education 47(2): 263–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bevan, Ryan. 2011. The question of conscientiousness and religious engagement in public schools. Studies in Philosophy and Education 30: 257–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell, Deanna M. 2010. Sidelines and separate spaces: Making education anti-racist for students of color. Race, Ethnicity, and Education 13(4): 473–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonilla-Silva, 2006. Racism without racists: Color-blind racism and the persistence of racial inequality in the United States. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Booth, Anthony R. 2012. All things considered duties to believe. Synthese 187: 509–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cahill, Anne, and Stephen Bloch-Schulman. 2012. Argumentation step-by-step: Learning critical thinking through deliberate practice. Teaching Philosophy 35(1): 41–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Case, Kim A., and Annette Hemmings. 2005. Distancing strategies: White women preservice teachers and antiracist curriculum. Urban Education 40(6): 606–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Code, Lorraine. 1987. Epistemic responsibility. Hanover, NH: Brown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Patricia H. 2008. Black feminist thought: Knowledge, consciousness, and the politics of empowerment. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Concepción, David, and Juli Eflin. 2009. Enabling change: Transformative and transgressive learning in feminist ethics and epistemology. Teaching Philosophy 32(2): 177–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delpit, Lisa. 2006. Other people’s children: Cultural conflict in the classroom. New York: New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine Z. 2013. Epistemic agency. Theory and Research in Education 11(2): 135–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friere, Paulo. 2005. Pedagogy of the oppressed, trans. Myra Bergman Ramos. New York: Continuum.

  • Gilson, Erinn. 2011. Vulnerability, ignorance, and oppression. Hypatia 26(2): 308–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, Nancy. 2010. If I know I can be wrong: The hidden history of epistemologies of ignorance. Philosophy Today 54: 122–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Liz. 2008. Dialogic pedagogy for social justice: A critical examination. Studies in Philosophy and Education 27: 137–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lugones, María C., and Elizabeth V. Spelman. 1983. Have we got a theory for you! Feminist theory, cultural imperialism, and the demand for ‘the woman’s voice’. Women’s Studies International Forum 6(6): 573–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malewski, Erik, and Nathalia Jaramillo (eds.). 2011. Epistemologies of ignorance in education. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, Connor. 2013. Epistemic responsibility and doxastic agency. Philosophical Issues 23: 132–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre, Alice. 1997. Making meaning of whiteness: Exploring racial identity with white teachers. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medina, José. 2013. The epistemology of resistance: Gender and racial oppression, epistemic injustice, and the social imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, JoAnne, and Marilyn Chamberlin. 2000. Woman are teachers, men are professors: A study of student perceptions. Teaching Sociology 28(4): 283–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 1997. The racial contract. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 1998. Blackness visible: Essays on philosophy and race. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 2007. White ignorance. In Race and epistemologies of ignorance, ed. Shannon Sullivan, and Nancy Tuana, 13–38. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montmarquet, James. 1993. Epistemic virtue and doxastic responsibility. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nottelman, Nikolaj. 2007. Blameworthy belief: A study in epistemic deontologism. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Puchner, Laurel, and Donyell Roseboro. 2011. Speaking of whiteness: Compromise as a purposeful strategy toward white students’ learning about race. Teaching in Higher Education 16(4): 377–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, Emily. 2013. The epistemic value of diversity. Journal of Philosophy of Education 47(2): 299–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Santas, Aristotelis. 2000. Teaching anti-racism. Studies in Philosophy and Education 19: 349–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroer, Jeanine W. 2007. Fighting imperviousness with vulnerability: Teaching in a climate of conservatism. Teaching Philosophy 30(2): 185–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steup, Matthias. 1988. The deontic conception of epistemic justification. Philosophical Studies 53(1): 65–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, Shannon. 2014. Good white people: The problem with middle-class white antiracism. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, Shannon, and Nancy Tuana (eds.). 2007. Race and epistemologies of ignorance. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teel, Karen. 2014. Getting out of the left lane: The possibility of white antiracist pedagogy. Teaching Theology and Religion 17(1): 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Audrey. 1997. For: Anti-racist education. Curriculum Inquiry 27(1): 7–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, Nancy. 2006. The speculum of ignorance: The women’s health movement and epistemologies of ignorance. Hypatia 21(3): 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, Nancy, and Shannon Sullivan. 2006. Introduction: Feminist epistemologies of ignorance. Hypatia 21.3: vii–ix.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yancy, George. 2008. Black bodies, white gazes: The continuing significance of race. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to foremost thank my students at Duke University, Warren Wilson College, and Vanderbilt University for teaching me daily and provoking me to take up this research and writing. I also thank Jennifer Ansley, Nolan Bennett, Stephen Bloch-Schulman, Jeff Edmonds, Seth Farber, Nora Hanagan, Jean Keller, José Medina, and Edward Piñuelas for their very helpful comments, as well as participants at the American Association of Philosophy Teachers 2014 Meeting, the Elon Philosophy Department Pedagogy Lunches, and the Duke Political Theory Workshop.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matt S. Whitt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Whitt, M.S. Other People’s Problems: Student Distancing, Epistemic Responsibility, and Injustice. Stud Philos Educ 35, 427–444 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-015-9484-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-015-9484-1

Keywords

Navigation