Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pftt2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-23T19:47:59.626Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Lawrence Dewan O.P. and Etienne Gilson: Reflections on Christian Philosophy's Continuing Relevance and Challenges

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2016 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Armour, Leslie, “Escaping Determinate Being: The Political Metaphysics of Jacques Maritain and Charles DeKonick” paper presented at the Canadian Maritain Association Meeting, Dominican University College, Ottawa (October 30, 2004)Google Scholar. See also Pope Leo XIII's Encyclical Letter Of Pope Leo XIII: On The Restoration Of Christian Philosophy According To The Mind Of St. Thomas Aquinas, The Angelic Doctor in St. Thomas Aquinas: Summa Theologica Vol.I QQ 1‐119 (Notre Dame: Christian Classics, 1920, 1948, 1981) pp. ix‐xviii. This encyclical which appears in full and serves as an introduction to this four volume text of St. Thomas also has special relevance for my ensuing discussion of Fr. Lawrence Dewan's and Etienne Gilson's Christian philosophies. This encyclical, I would argue, serves as one of, if not the most formative authoritative Church instruction for their respective projects.

2 Fr.Dewan, Lawrence O.P., Thomas Aquinas, Wisdom, and Human Dignity: Philosophy and Beyond (Houston, Texas: University of St. Thomas, Aquinas Lecture, October 2013)Google Scholar.

3 According to Fr. Dewan, St. Thomas’ exemplary achievement as a teacher of humanity is in his artful and skilful balancing of reason and faith, and thus of the philosophical and theological in an unsurpassable manner.

4 Schmitz, Kenneth, The Texture of Being (Washington, D.C: The Catholic University of America Press, 2007) pp. 284–5Google Scholar. The modern problematic I'm referring to can be said simply to be “freedom” – and this “freedom” as a topic must lead one into a reflection on one's own life and concrete circumstances and the decisions and choices made and to be made. Such reflection cannot be sustained meaningfully unless the practical and personal is seriously confronted. This then is freedom's inexorable connection with the “concrete” in the modern problematic. … and it is a very troublesome problematic for most academic thinkers and scholars and their penchant for abstract thought.

5 This overview of Gilson's philosophy is guided by Schmitz's, Kenneth, What Has Clio to Do with Athena? Etienne Gilson: Historian and Philosopher (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1987) pp. 124Google Scholar.

6 For Gilson and other existential Thomists, the most relevant and readily available text that presents a sustained argument believed to support the existential reading of St. Thomas is in his “On Being and Essence”. See St.Aquinas, Thomas, “On Being and Essence” in McDermott, Timothy, ed., Thomas Aquinas: Selected Philosophical Writings (Oxford University Press, 1998) pp. 90113Google Scholar.

My own summary gloss based upon this text and most relevant for this crucial point in the debate is that ‐

Form marks out species within a genus and matter marks out individuals within a species. (2) The very form which an intellect is has potentiality for the existence it requires from God and the acquired existence actualizes it. (4) In created intellectual substances, essence is unlimited by matter from below but limited in its existence from above. The human mind receives its individuality in actualizing the body to which it is joined. This individuality does not perish upon decomposition but this very existence (as act) that is individuated by the body remains eternally individuated by being firstly made the form of this body. (5)

Substantial form has no existence of its own apart from the material upon which it supervenes so that the existence of the self‐sufficient thing awaits composition of the two into something essentially one – an essence.

(6)

Of equal importance in this text and highly relevant to this argument, is St. Thomas’ distinction between real being and logic and how the logical entertainment of form gives us nothing concrete until there is the presence of existence, and how the logical concepts of our analysis of things are ultimately defied by the simplicity of this divine source of the existence in real things, to which the entire discourse is dedicated.

Logic gives us nothing essentially one (that is itself, that is its own and no other) and joining logically results in nothing to which the concept of genus or species can be strictly (concretely) applied. Clearly then, the essence is realized concretely in substances both composite and simple and in their incidental properties. It is also clear how logical concepts of generality arise in all except the first supremely simple Being whose simplicity defies categorization and definition and in whom may this discourse have its end and fulfillment. Amen!

(6)

7 See Kenneth Schmitz's, The Texture of Being for an updated treatment both sympathetic and critical of Gilson's doctrine of being, See especially his papers “Enriching the Copula”, “Created Receptivity and the Philosophy of the Concrete”, and “The Solidarity of Personalism and the Metaphysics of Existential Act”. In so many respects Schmitz has shown convincingly, in my view, the continuing relevance and significance of Gilson for contemporary thought especially for those thinkers who are trying to engage this thought out of a Christian background and formation.

8 In this excursus into deep ontology, I remain closer to Gilson's position than that of Fr. Dewan's; and yet I believe Fr. Dewan's position warrants a careful treatment, and I hope to show some basis for an interpretation of complementarity rather than conflict. Much of what follows is based upon Fr. Dewan's paper “Thomas Aquinas, Creation, and Two Historians” in Laval Theologique et Philosophique, Vol. 50, (1994) pp. 363‐387. See also Fr.Dewan's, Form And Being: Studies in Thomistic Metaphysics (Washington: The Catholic University of America Press, 2006)Google Scholar.

9 Fr. Dewan illustrates this intimacy between form and the act of existence in the example of the ordering of the letters T, C, A which in becoming ordered as “CAT”, i.e. taking the form of “CAT”, supposedly becomes almost identical with the existence of the word “CAT”, i.e. almost identical with its act of existence. (See Fr. Dewans’ discussion of this illustration in his paper “Form and Esse in Caused Things” in his Form and Being: Studies in Thomistic Metaphysics (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2006) pp. 188‐204.) This argument is helpful for clarifying the meaning of his point, but I do not believe it to be supportive of what he wants to argue here regarding the role of the act of existence. One simply cannot say that the form is truly identical with the act of existence because of the problem of “CAT” then supposedly having to be identical with the word “ACT” in some manner, which simply is not the fact of the matter, but rather “ACT” being another formation of the letters T, C, A also has its own distinctive act of existence. So if we must retain the real distinction between existence and essence, being and form, it seems likely that Gilson's (and Maritain's) attribution of some degree of primacy to the act of existence over that of form may also have some sense to it metaphysically and ontologically and in truth is definitely more than a “troublesome fiction”. This further has consequences for the relationship of “practice and theory” as well as “being and truth”.

10 Gilson resonated with aspects of Heidegger's critique of Western philosophy's forgetfulness of being. Lawrence Shook recounts in his biography of Gilson (Etienne Gilson (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1984) p. 227) how Gilson was moved to tears by a Heidegger lecture which he attended at Harvard. This anecdotal note may provide a hermeneutical key for grasping the significance of this issue between Fr. Dewan and Gilson over the primacy of form (essence) versus the primacy of existential act (esse) in our sense of being. Gilson having begun his philosophical career with the study of Descartes before discovering the philosophical riches of the medievals and of St. Thomas in particular, had a pronounced sensitivity to and interest in the modern problematic and its efforts to reconcile the moderns’ turn to the knowing subject with the ancients’ concern for being as object. Heidegger, in Gilson's view was trying to recall something in philosophy's beginning that has been forgotten or eclipsed because of a preoccupation with, and dominance of something else. Because of certain leadings in Plato, philosophy has been concerned with the “seeing of reason” made possible by the “light of truth” ultimately best secured by theory for us as thinking beings. At its worst, this line of development has consummated in a type of one sided monological and objectifying philosophical thought and thus requires a strategic post‐modern reaction to this development in philosophy. This conception of philosophy in its preoccupation with essences, it is argued, is too often forgetful of our existential situation and it is this distortion that leads to such a profound error in orientation and balance. It is an error because this “light of truth” presupposes and actually depends upon the “openings or occasions” of existence. There is no actual light without, what we might call the existential opening for its occurrence. We of course are speaking metaphorically but the relevance of the insight, I would strongly argue, can be tested in any careful phenomenological reflection upon our actual practice and experience. (See Martin Heidegger's essay “The End of Philosophy and The Task of Thinking” in David Krell ed., Martin Heidegger Basic Writings. (New York: Harper and Row, 1977) pp. 373‐392; See alsoSchurmann, Reiner. Heidegger on Being and Acting: From Principles To Anarchy (Bloomington: Indiana University Press) pp. 235245Google Scholar on the “practical apriori” in Heidegger.

11 This dense summary of Gilson's position is based upon his treatment of the topic in his Thomism: The Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 2002)Google Scholar see especially pp. 137‐174; also see Gilson's classic discussion of the topic Being and Some Philosophers (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1949)Google Scholar see especially his section on Aristotle pp. 40‐51; 154‐167.

12 In elaborating upon the existential dimension of this problem of the one and the many in a way that remains relevant to our everyday experience, we have followed closely the arguments developed by Gerard Smith, who in our view has ably developed Gilson's Christian existentialism, in his The Philosophy Of Being (New York: MacMillan, 1961) especially his Chapter 4, pp. 56‐79. If we are intent upon conducting a philosophical discussion of deeper metaphysical and ontological scope we must be prepared to consider how what we are saying applies inescapably to our own actual situations and lets say as discussion or seminar participants. The first fact is that there are several of us. There is a plurality of philosophers who each exist as human existents. To be an existent is to be one existent yet there are many existents – Leslie, Frank, Hugh, and Maxime. We all as individuals have the fact we are existents in common yet this commonness is not such as to cause Leslie, Frank, Hugh, and Maxime to be one. The status of being an existent clearly involves the enjoyment of one's identity. This is the unity of being and yet no one of us as existent so fully enjoys the status to the exclusion of the others’ enjoyment. Thus Leslie, Frank, Hugh, and Maxime are a multiplicity. In this sense, being has the status of one and many as existents and we must confront the question why are there any existents at all? Frank or Maxime might argue that this is a fool's question – why should the fact of our situation of multiplicity and unity as beings raise such a question? But such a protest means one does not appreciate the significance of our situation metaphysically – that the status of being an existent is not the prerogative of the lot of us. There is nothing in the status of being “Frank” or “Maxime”, as an existent, that demands logically there be Leslie, Frank, Hugh, and Maxime. To say we have no need to explain there being more than one because to be an existent is simply to be more than one is to say in effect that the many is one. This is to assume a monistic ontology metaphysically. Yet we agree do we not, that our actual experience shows us that there are many of us? And so we must ask why are there many of us? If Frank were the only existent the question doesn't arise – he is the One or he is not, and if not, he would not be present to raise the question and if he was present he'd be content with being the One for to be an existent is to be himself. But we know this is not the situation for there is Leslie, Maxime, and Hugh who in our status as existents do not explain our multiplicity. Why are there many of us as existents? We see now that to be an existent there is no need that there be many of us. To be Leslie as existent there is no need that there be Hugh, Frank, and Maxime. Yet there are many of us, why? The formal answer is that there are many existents ‐ Leslie, Frank, Hugh, and Maxime because they are caused to be many existents by a cause that is able to do so. We now see that there are Leslie, Frank, Hugh, and Maxime and the reason cannot be because to be any one of us is to be many nor can it be that to be many existents is to be any one of us. Trying to explain the one and the many either way one's mind goes blank because the status of being an existent gets lost either way. The intelligibility of being a real existent requires we avoid thinking the one as many or the many as one and instead consider the many as caused.

As there is nothing in the status of number that demands it be actually odd or even, so too there is nothing in the status of being an existent that demands it be caused or uncaused. All that is required is that it exists. Causality is not the reason there is an existent. It is not necessarily a principle of being; it is only a principle of an existent that shows itself to be caused. Causality is a principle of caused being and that a being be caused must be shown just as the oddness or evenness of a number must be shown in this or that actual number. Thus Maxime's status of being an existent is also enjoyed individually by Leslie, Frank, and Hugh, no one of which is the other. This multiplicity of existents demands a cause as many. Because Leslie, Frank, Hugh, and Maxime all share in the status of being an existent, the intelligibility of this sharing or sameness as existents requires that one of us be the cause of the others, or that we must all be caused by another existent. This dependency in the contingency of our existence cannot go on to infinity so there must be a necessary being as the grounding cause of all of us dependent existents. There is plurality in Leslie, Frank, Hugh, and Maxime sharing in existence as existents because there is One above many as the cause of many. (Norris Clarke makes the same important point in his Explorations In Metaphysics (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame, 1994), p. 94.)Google Scholar.

13 For a cogent and penetrating discussion of the conflict between essentialism and existentialism, and the centrality of this question “why do many things exist rather than not?” for the tradition of Christian philosophy see Gerard Smith's, Natural Theology (New York: The MacMillan Co. 1951) pp. 11‐35.

14 See Dewan, Lawrence O.P., “The Individual as a Mode of Being” in Form And Being: Studies in Thomistic Metaphysics ((Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2006) pp. 237238Google Scholar. At this point, it needs to be acknowledged that Fr. Dewans's Thomistic scholarship is simply formidable in its scope and precision. The issue in large part can be cast as one of scholarship ‐ just what is the correct reading of Thomas's texts? I simply am not competent to wade into this aspect of the argument, but I will suggest that there is also the question of the philosophical merit of Gilson's position in itself, irrespective of whether Thomas meant what Gilson says he meant. And there is also the even more perplexing question of whether complex texts such as those we have of Aristotle and Thomas, can have in their depths, meanings and significance that the author himself may not have been fully aware of ? Leo Sweeny, in his Christian Philosophy: Greek, Medieval, Contemporary Reflections (New York: Peter Lang, 1997), see especially Ch. 19, gives a relatively exhaustive examination of the textual evidence of Thomas’ position regarding existence and essence in the doctrine of being. In my reading of Sweeney, I conclude that the issue remains a complex matter of scholarly exegesis, and so retains a sufficient element of ambiguity for one to conclude that at a minimum Gilson's position is not a troublesome fiction and remains of continuing relevance for Christian philosophy and philosophy more generally.

15 This imaginatively constructed response is based upon arguments found in Gilson's, Etienne, “Being and Essences” in his Christian Philosophy (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1993) pp. 101119Google Scholar.

16 Owens, Joseph, An Elementary Christian Metaphysics (Houston: Center For Thomistic Studies, 2003) pp. 4548Google Scholar; see also my Dialogical Practice and the Ontology of the Human Person (New York: Vantage Press, 2010). This existential argument has important theological implications, in my view, for at least understanding the deep interconnection of the ontological and historical in any proper understanding of the Christian mystery. Apart from an awareness of certain real events in the past, the notion of Jesus’ resurrection as an historical reality remains only supposition and not real knowledge. The image of events surrounding the resurrection and the awareness of it belonging to our present consciousness do not in themselves bear the mark of the past. If we can and do link them with the historical past, it is because we are also aware of an experience from the past resembling these present images. This means that this act of individual and collective Christian memory needs to be explained. In our ordinary knowledge of change, we can reflect upon our dependence on memory to help us in our account. The impression of change as movement, for instance, involves a complex relation between sensation, perception, and memory. For example, a melodic phrase in our common experience of music is not the hearing of notes one by one without relation to one another, rather all notes in some sense are at the same time – simultaneously present to consciousness, and yet there is an awareness of their succession and consequent temporal relations. Memory is involved for the past notes continuity with the present phrase. There is in the origins of this experience no elaborate process of logical inference required. Here in our ordinary experience of change, is a good sign of the existence of what we might call intuitive memory or intuition in memory. There are then common instances of intuitive memory. But we must ask what are the conditions for such intuitive memory – of there being some basis for an intuitive knowledge of Jesus’ actual historical resurrection? One condition relevant for present knowledge of Jesus’ resurrection is the presence in consciousness of factors resembling the historical events surrounding the resurrection. There is in some sense a revival in our present of the historical events of the resurrection in conjunction with our consciousness of the Church's similar and resembling images, signs, and symbols that can only be explained through an intuition of the being of these events through this collective or communal memory of the Church. What is crucial here is that factors causally determining the Church's present signs and imagery are the actual historical events themselves that surround Jesus’ resurrection. This is not in its origins an inference from effect to cause but rather an intuitive awareness of the continuing presence of Jesus’ historical resurrection providing the basis for what we are calling resemblance or similarity in this present awareness called memory. The complex phenomena of our ordinary memory are inexplicable without some fundamental intuition of the past because of a direct communication of the past in our present caused by actual past events. It is then the actual and historical resurrection of Christ, which serves as the causal determinant of the present signs and images resembling it – such signs and images being persons as members, sacred texts, sacraments, and symbols of the Christian Church, or more accurately being the body of the Church itself as sacrament and sign. Also, without the notion of substance, memory alone becomes the source of my Christian identity rather than its consequent. But memory is not of events in the past but of the events in your or my past, and in the past of other persons with whom we are in relationship within the tradition. My personal identity is conceived as a continuing substance or subject of agency that is revealed phenomenologically by memory but in its actual identity is the ontological source and principle of actuality for the possibility of personal memory and not its result. We can say then on the basis of this deeper account that there is an intuitive awareness of the historical resurrection of Jesus that is the cause of our present signs and symbols of remembrance as Church. There is the knowledge of this resemblance and similarity based upon the intuition of causal efficacy in remembrance. There is an intuitive awareness for the Church and its members of the historical event of Jesus’ resurrection as cause of our knowledge of it in and through present memory. This account also assumes that from the very beginning of Christianity there was always a primary external or objective authority existing alongside the subjective authority of individual consciousnesses and consciences that in this matter of faith can serve only as secondary sources at best. This primary and foremost authority has always had an historical dimension in the person and paschal mystery of Jesus Christ and subsequently in the order of the Church's deposit of faith, apostolic succession, and teaching authority. (See Hawkins, D. B., The Criticism of Experience (London: Sheed and Ward, 1945)Google Scholar see especially pp.97‐106 for an incisive realist treatment of memory in terms of Gilson's ontology and that I am arguing here has great relevance for the theological doctrine of sacramental presence.)