Skip to main content
Log in

Character Analysis in Cladistics: Abstraction, Reification, and the Search for Objectivity

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Acta Biotheoretica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

An Erratum to this article was published on 20 February 2009

Abstract

The dangers of character reification for cladistic inference are explored. The identification and analysis of characters always involves theory-laden abstraction—there is no theory-free “view from nowhere.” Given theory-ladenness, and given a real world with actual objects and processes, how can we separate robustly real biological characters from uncritically reified characters? One way to avoid reification is through the employment of objectivity criteria that give us good methods for identifying robust primary homology statements. I identify six such criteria and explore each with examples. Ultimately, it is important to minimize character reification, because poor character analysis leads to dismal cladograms, even when proper phylogenetic analysis is employed. Given the deep and systemic problems associated with character reification, it is ironic that philosophers have focused almost entirely on phylogenetic analysis and neglected character analysis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper I will bracket issues regarding classification and taxonomy. My concern is with the character analysis and the phylogenetic analysis of cladistic inference.

  2. Moreover, both can be descriptive as well as normative. Indeed, the project of this paper is ultimately normative. The objectivity criteria developed in Sect. (6) are gleaned from good practice and are norms for how a cladist should engage in proper character analysis. (I thank Elliot Sober for pushing me on this.)

  3. Although I am one of its defenders, the latter interpretation of the co-construction of epistemology/methodology and ontology is, strictly speaking, optional for the argument of this paper. For instance, a strong philosophical realist who distinguishes epistemological from ontological matters (e.g., Devitt 1991) can still read this paper for insight into how scientists go about discovering characters that exist in the world independently of science. Under this realist light, practice-based investigations of scientific reasoning are useful particularly because they indicate the myriad ways in which biased scientists produce representations that deviate from a true or ideal description of the world. Some strong realists (“the world is difficult to know” realist) could then find my project interesting because it gives us a handle on the many difficulties we always encounter in the discovery process. Other strong realists, however, would of course be free to downplay my project because it does not address ontological questions directly (whatever exactly that would mean), either in science or in a philosophical rendition of science, but instead “conflates” ontological and epistemological matters by focusing on practices. A final note in this context. Strong realism is not the only sort of theory-based philosophical analysis available. Other sorts of theory-based investigations insist on a much more nuanced relation—social, Kantian or otherwise—between epistemology/methodology and ontology (e.g., Kuhn 1970; Goodman 1978; Putnam 1981; Friedman 1999). Thus, the (i) theory-based versus practice-based philosophical analysis distinction is emphatically not co-extensive, let alone identical with, the (ii) epistemology/methodology versus ontology dichotomy on which the strong realist intently insists. That is, a theory-based investigation need not be premised on distinction (ii).

  4. Strictly speaking, there is an important link between character analysis and phylogenetic analysis: character coding. That is, even once we have abstracted characters and character-states, we need to write them out in proper form for a data matrix. There is significant debate regarding the best way to formalize characters: e.g., whether we should use “present” / ”absent” or focus primarily on positive statements of character-state properties [e.g., Pleijel 1995; Fitzhugh 2006, 2008 (see options A-F on p. 275 of 2006); Sereno 2007; see also Freudenstein 2005 who usefully distinguishes characters from character-states in terms of their exhibiting either “paralogous” or “orthologous” relationships (sensu Fitch 1970), respectively, with other characters or character-states; the titles of Pimentel and Riggins 1987 and Hawkins 2000 suggests that they will write about primary homology assessment, but in fact they each end up addressing character coding]. Character coding as a problem is clearly important, but well beyond the scope of this paper as it concerns the link between character and phylogenetic analysis, rather than character analysis sensu stricto. Put differently, I am concerned with the abstraction and reification process that occurs prior to writing out the characters and character-states in the data matrix. Of course, I realize that the two problems (i.e., “primary homology”/character assessment problem, and coding problem) are not independent (e.g., Stevens 2000), but conceptual progress can still be made by focusing exclusively on the former. And certainly the former cannot be reduced to the latter (contra Fitzhugh and Sereno)! Another issue I will not address here is the polarization of characters (e.g., Patterson 1982; Nixon and Carpenter 1993; Brusca and Brusca 2003). Since methods of polarization (e.g., outgroup comparison) do not affect the nature or quality of the characters, but attend to which of two or more character-states is postulated to be ancestral/synapomorphic (a topic crucial to phylogenetic, but not character, analysis), this important topic is not germane to this article.

  5. The establishment of the polarity of a character state—i.e., the determination of a particular state as either ancestral or derived—is done through ontogeny or outgroup comparison, or both. Under ontogenetic analysis, the character state that appears first during development is considered the primitive character state (e.g., a two-chambered as opposed to a four-chambered vertebrate heart). Under outgroup comparison, the character state that is most frequent in groups other than the ones being investigated is considered the primitive state (see Radinsky 1987, p. 6).

  6. A word about “true System or Tree” or “true cladogram”. As argued in Sect. 2, I adopt a sort of epistemically-conditioned realism here, rather than an instrumentalism. However, the argument in this section goes through regardless of one’s commitments in the realism debates. There is presumably a fact of the matter about the pattern and process of the evolution of life; there is presumably a true System or Tree. This is so regardless of how difficult it is to infer it or whether there is an “irreducible” human-abstraction component to it. I trust that the reader will grant this. (See Vergara-Silva, this issue, for discussion and healthy skepticism about such a view.) Now, given that there is a fact of the matter about patter and process, do we need to use explicit methodologies and criteria for character analysis in order to get close to this cladogram? This paper argues that we should and can have recourse to objectivity criteria for character analysis (or else we will miss the mark). In contrast, many others (solution 1, see below) argue that even granting the in principle existence of a true cladogram, explicit criteria are not necessary in our search for it. A final point. I am here concerned specifically with those regions of the universal history of life where cladistic assumptions hold (e.g., vertical inheritance and branching modification with descent, as is the case for chordate evolution). It is at best unclear what the true System or Tree would be for domains of the history of life (e.g., early microbial evolution) where cladistic assumptions do not hold in particular because there is horizontal gene transfer (e.g., Woese 2000; Doolittle and Bapteste 2007; O’Malley and Dupré 2007). I bracket this important issue here.

  7. Although I focus on morphological data in this paper, I cannot here avoid talking about molecular data. As we shall see, the latter are hardly a magical bullet for cladistic analysis (Patterson 1988; Patterson et al. 1993; but see Scotland et al. 2003).

  8. Mishler (2005, p. 665) provides a useful “pro and con” table for molecular and morphological data. Molecular data have at least two disadvantages: they have neither “complexity and comparability” nor “many possible character states.”

  9. These correspond to two of the four aspects of objectivity in Lloyd 1995 (see also Lloyd 1996).

  10. I have not employed the interesting character rejection criteria from Poe and Wiens (2000) (see also Sereno 2007), such as high character variation or substantial missing data, because their criteria do not get at primary homology claims or character analysis as such. Rather, they are investigating something more like character coding (see note 4 above). Stevens (1991, 2000) discusses some of the reification problems entailed by such criteria.

  11. And, I suspect, reification, but showing that would be part of another project.

  12. I realize that some will disagree because they will only want to make “secondary homology” and “character” co-extensive, under the cladistic paradigm. I will simply say that the motivation for employing objectivity criteria is that they give us good characters—i.e., ones that are highly likely to be synapomorphic. Recall [Sect. 3] that I take issue with those who abstract any character whatsoever, without applying the objectivity criteria. Put differently, using objectivity criteria brings primary homology claims closer to secondary homology affirmations.

  13. They could be considered homologous at a higher level of resolution: qua vertebrae of vertebrates, in general. Rieppel and Kearney 2006 make this exact point (p. 101). It is generally true that homology claims need to be relativized to a particular level of comparison: e.g., bird and bat wings are not homologous qua wings, but they are homologous qua tetrapod limbs. For the purposes of this paper, and for stipulating the same “character”, I will focus primarily on low, concrete levels of resolution (e.g., wings rather than tetrapod limbs) and will not further discuss this important issue.

  14. This is also the case for molecular characters. These also receive biological meaning from investigations into the causal reasons (in historically-conditioned genetic systems) for sequence similarity.

  15. Note that this criterion is pragmatic as well as epistemic, sensu stricto. That is, it concerns both (1) the practices of discovering and developing primary homology claims, as well as the use and usefulness of such claims (pragmatic), and (2) the truth of primary homology assertions [i.e., the truth relation between character claims and the (potentially co-constructed) world] (epistemic). (On epistemic versus pragmatic virtues, see, e.g., van Fraassen 1980.) That this criterion is pragmatic should be evident (Sober, personal communication). But I argue that it is also epistemic. Consider the following gross idealization of the practice of character analysis: each phylogenetically-relevant discipline produces its own list of characters. For instance, comparative morphology, molecular genetics, and developmental biology have different “partitioning frames” (Winther 2006c) and each therefore articulates a different list. Given these lists, inter-disciplinary communication has at least two aims. First, it attempts to find the characters that are shared across disciplinary contexts. It thereby produces a collated list of strongly empirically adequate characters—i.e., of robust characters. Since the empirical adequacy of a shared character is bolstered through inter-disciplinary communication, this criterion has epistemic weight. Second, communication aims to identify the empirical relations among characters that are not shared across contexts (e.g., causal or common-cause relations). Discovering relations among non-shared characters also increases the empirical adequacy of the total inter-disciplinary list of characters. Again, inter-disciplinary communication is epistemically relevant.

  16. Although I cannot argue for this further here, the indeterminacy and the under determination of rule application is a generalized worry relevant to all of science. Despite indeterminacy and under determination—explored by Quine, Goodman, and “Kripkenstein”, as well as other philosophers—scientists productively employ rules, heuristics, and methodology that allow science to progress. This suggests that the strong skepticism about rule application and rule existence entertained by Richards is unwarranted.

  17. It is important to note that Quine was a thoroughgoing empiricist and naturalist. That is, he was skeptical about the analytical role, even coherence, of notions like “cause”, “disposition” or “the real”. And yet, he felt that science was progressing—its inductions were to a large extent successful. I will not delve further into important and finer points of Quine scholarship.

  18. Richard Boyd (1999) also has an account of how natural kinds can be grounded causally (mechanistically). Although his “homeostatic property cluster kind” account differs radically with Quine and Putnam with respect to both the semantic tightness of the intension, and the uniformity of the extension, of natural kind terms, he shares their view that (a broader) similarity of the extension of objects or processes of natural kinds should be explained by a causal (mechanistic) account.

References

  • Beatty J (1982) Classes and cladists. Syst Zool 31:25–34. doi:10.2307/2413411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonde N (1977) Cladistic classification as applied to vertebrates. In: Hecht MK, Goodbody PC, Hecht BM (eds) Major patterns in vertebrate evolution. Plenum Press, New York, pp 741–804

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonde N (1996) “Moderne systematik—fylogeni og klassifikation”. In: Bonde N, Hoffmeyer J (eds) Naturens historiefortællere, vol 2, 2nd edn. Udviklingsideens historie, Copenhagen, 127–181

  • Boyd R (1999) Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species. New interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 141–185

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady RH (1985) On the independence of systematics. Cladistics 1:113–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bremer B, Jansen RK, Oxelman B, Backlund M, Lantz H, Kim K-J (1999) More characters or more taxa for a robust phylogeny. Case study from the coffee family (Rubiaceae). Syst Biol 48:413–435

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I, Griffiths PE (2007) The importance of homology for biology and philosophy (Editors’ introduction to the special issue). Biol Philos 22:633–641. doi:10.1007/s10539-007-9094-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks DR (1996) Explanations of homoplasy at different levels of biological organization. In: Sanderson MJ, Hufford L (eds) Homoplasy. The recurrence of similarity in evolution. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 3–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Brower AVZ, Schawaroch V (1996) Three steps of homology assessment. Cladistics 12:265–272

    Google Scholar 

  • Brusca RC, Brusca GJ (2003) Invertebrates, 2nd edn. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryant HN (1989) An evaluation of cladistic and character analyses as hypothetico-deductive procedures, and the consequences for character weighting. Syst Zool 38:214–227. doi:10.2307/2992283

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1989) Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Colless DH (1985) On “character” and related terms. Syst Zool 34:229–233. doi:10.2307/2413331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver C (2007) Explaining the brain. Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1854) A monograph on the sub-class Cirripedia, with figures of all species. The Balanidae, (or sessile cirripedes); the Verrucidae, etc., etc., etc.: 1–684 + pls, vol 2. Ray Society, London, pp 1–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1859/2001) On the origin of species by means of natural selection or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

  • De Pinna MCC (1991) Concepts and tests of homology in the cladistic paradigm. Cladistics 7:367–394. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.1991.tb00045.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Queiroz A, Donoghue MJ, Kim J (1995) Separate versus combined analysis of phylogenetic evidence. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 26:657–681. doi:10.1146/annurev.es.26.110195.003301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Queiroz K (1985) The ontogenetic method for determining character polarity and its relevance to phylogenetic systematics. Syst Zool 34:280–299. doi:10.2307/2413148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (1991) Realism and truth. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Doolittle WF, Bapteste E (2007) Pattern pluralism and the tree of life hypothesis. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104:2043–2049. doi:10.1073/pnas.0610699104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (2002) Is ‘natural kind’ a natural kind term? Monist 85:29–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge N, Cracraft J (1980) Phylogenetic patterns and the evolutionary process. Method and theory in comparative biology. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2001) The poverty of the Linnean hierarchy. A philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Farris J, Kluge AG (1979) A botanical clique. Syst Zool 28:400–411. doi:10.2307/2412596

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsenstein J (1982) Numerical methods for inferring evolutionary trees. Q Rev Biol 57:379–404. doi:10.1086/412935

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsenstein J (2003) Inferring phylogenies. Sinauer Press, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitch WM (1970) Distinguishing homologous from analogous proteins. Syst Zool 19:99–113. doi:10.2307/2412448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzhugh K (2006) The philosophical basis of character coding for the inference of phylogenetic hypotheses. Zool Scr 35:261–286. doi:10.1111/j.1463-6409.2006.00229.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzhugh K (2008) Clarifying the role of character loss in phylogenetic inference. Zool Scr 37:561–569. doi:10.1111/j.1463-6409.2008.00338.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freudenstein JV (2005) Characters, states and homology. Syst Biol 54:965–973. doi:10.1080/10635150500354654

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1999) The dynamics of reason. CSLI Publications, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fristrup K (1992) Character. Current usages. In: Keller EF, Lloyd EA (eds) Keywords in evolutionary biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 45–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Fristrup K (2001) A history of character concepts in evolutionary biology. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 13–35

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin M (1984) ‘Definition’, ‘character’, and other equivocal terms. Syst Zool 33:104–110. doi:10.2307/2413135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan S (2002) Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philos Sci 69:S342–S353. doi:10.1086/341857

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman N (1978) Ways of worldmaking. Harvester Press Limited, Hassocks

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant T, Kluge AG (2004) Transformation series as an ideographic character concept. Cladistics 20:23–31. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.2004.00003.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (2007) Natural kinds: Rosy Dawn, Scholastic Twilight. R Inst Philos Suppl 61:203–240

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding S (1995) ‘Strong Objectivity’: a response to the new objectivity question. Synthese 104:331–349. doi:10.1007/BF01064504

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Härlin M (1999) The logical priority of the tree over characters and some of its consequences for taxonomy. Biol J Linn Soc Lond 68:497–503. doi:10.1111/j.1095-8312.1999.tb01185.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins JA (2000) A survey of primary homology assessment: different botanists perceive and define characters in different ways. In: Scotland R, Pennington RT (eds) Homology and systematics. Coding characters for phylogenetic analysis. Taylor and Francis, London, pp 22–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins JA, Hughes CE, Scotland RW (1997) Primary homology assessment, characters and character states. Cladistics 13:275–283. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.1997.tb00320.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hennig W (1950) Gründzuge einer Theorie der Phylogenetischen Systematik. Deutscher Zentralverlag, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig W (1966) Phylogenetic systematics. University of llinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillis DM, Wiens JJ (2000) Molecules versus morphology in systematics. In: Wiens JJ (ed) Phylogenetic analyses of morphological data. Smithsonian Institution Press, Washington, DC, pp 1–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillis DM, Huelsenbeck JP, Cunningham CW (1994) Application and accuracy of molecular phylogenies. Science 264:671–677. doi:10.1126/science.8171318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hillis DM, Moritz C, Mable BK (1996) Molecular systematics, 2nd edn. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull D (1988) Science as a process. An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine N (1967) The concept of homology in biology. Br J Philos Sci 18:125–139. doi:10.1093/bjps/18.2.125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jardine N (1969) The observational and theoretical components of homology: A study based on the morphology of the dermal skull-roofs of rhipidistian fishes. Biol J Linn Soc Lond 1:327–361. doi:10.1111/j.1095-8312.1969.tb00125.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones MR (2005) Idealization and abstraction: a framework. In: Jones MR, Cartwright N (eds) Idealization XII: correcting the model. Idealization and abstraction in the sciences (Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities, vol 86). Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp 173–217

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearney M, Rieppel O (2006) Rejecting ‘the given’ in systematics. Cladistics 22:369–377. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.2006.00110.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi MA (1998) Natural kinds and crosscutting categories. J Philos 95:33–50. doi:10.2307/2564567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kluge AG (1989) A concern for evidence and a phylogenetic hypothesis of relationships among Epicrates (Boidea, Serpentes). Syst Zool 38:7–25. doi:10.2307/2992432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch M (2002) Knowledge by agreement. The programme of communitarian epistemology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lecointre G, Deleporte P (2005) Total evidence requires exclusion of phylogenetically misleading data. Zool Scr 34:101–117. doi:10.1111/j.1463-6409.2005.00168.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2008) Growing weed, producing knowledge. An epistemological history of Arabidopsis thaliana. Hist Philos Life Sci 29:55–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. Am Sci 54:421–431

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (2006) Strategies of abstraction. Biol Philos 21:741–755. doi:10.1007/s10539-006-9052-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R, Lewontin R (1985) The dialectical biologist. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (2001) Foreword. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp xvii–xxiii

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin R, Levins R (2007) Biology under the influence. Dialectical essays on ecology, agriculture, and health. Monthly Review Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (1988) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (1995) Objectivity and the double standard for feminist epistemologies. Synthese 104:351–381. doi:10.1007/BF01064505

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (1996) Science and anti-science: objectivity and its real enemies. In: Nelson LH, Nelson J (eds) Feminism, science and the philosophy of science. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 217–259

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino H (1995) Gender, politics, and the theoretical virtues. Synthese 104:383–397. doi:10.1007/BF01064506

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino H (2002) The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Love AC Typology reconfigured: from the metaphysics of essentialism to the epistemology of representation. Acta Biotheor (This issue)

  • McManus Guerrero F (2006) Desacuerdos racionales, selección de modelos y sistemática filogenética. Masters Thesis, (Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, México DF)

  • McManus Guerrero F Rational disagreements in phylogenetics (This Issue)

  • Mindell DP (1991) Similarity and congruence as criteria for molecular homology. Mol Biol Evol 8:897–900

    Google Scholar 

  • Mishler BD (2005) The logic of the data matrix in phlogenetic analysis. In: Albert VA (ed) Parsimony, phylogeny, and genomics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 57–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Neff NA (1986) A rational basis for a priori character weighting. Syst Zool 35:110–123. doi:10.2307/2413295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson G (1978) Ontogeny, phylogeny, paleontology, and the biogenetic law. Syst Zool 27:324–345. doi:10.2307/2412883

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson G, Platnick N (1981) Systematics and biogeography. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman WA, Ross A (1976) Revision of the balanomorph barnacles; including a catalogue of the species. Mem San Diego Soc Nat Hist 9:1–108

    Google Scholar 

  • Nixon KC, Carpenter JM (1993) On outgroups. Cladistics 9:413–426. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.1993.tb00234.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2007) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley M, Dupré J (2007) Size doesn’t matter: towards a more inclusive philosophy of biology. Biol Philos 22:155–191. doi:10.1007/s10539-006-9031-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patterson C (1981) The goals, uses, and assumptions of cladistic analysis. Talk given at the second annual meeting of the Willi Hennig society, Ann Arbor

  • Patterson C (1982) Morphological characters and homology. In: Joysey KA, Friday AE (eds) Problems in phylogenetic reconstruction. Academic Press, London, pp 21–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson C (1988) Homology in classical and molecular biology. Mol Biol Evol 5:603–625

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson C, Williams DM, Humpries CJ (1993) Congruence between molecular and morphological phylogenies. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 24:153–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pimentel RA, Riggins R (1987) The nature of cladistic data. Cladistics 3:201–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Platnick NI (1977) Cladograms, phylogenetic trees, and hypothesis testing. Syst Zool 26:438–442. doi:10.2307/2412799

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pleijel F (1995) On character coding for phylogeny reconstruction. Cladistics 11:309–315. doi:10.1016/0748-3007(95)90018-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poe S, Wiens JJ (2000) Character selection and the methodology of morphological phylogenetics. In: Wiens JJ (ed) Phylogenetic analysis of morphological data. Smithsonian Institution Press, Washington DC, pp 20–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1963) Conjectures and refutations: the growth of scientific knowledge. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1996 (1975)) The meaning of ‘meaning. In: Pessin A, Goldberg S (eds) The Twin Earth Chronicles. Twenty Years of Reflection on Hilary Putnam’s “The Meaning of ‘Meaning”, Armonk, M.E. Sharpe, pp 3–52

  • Putnam H (1981) Reason, truth and history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WV (1977/1969) Natural kinds. In: Schwartz SP (ed) Naming, necessity and natural kinds, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, pp 155–175

  • Radinsky LB (1987) The evolution of vertebrate design. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Remane A (1952) Die Grundlagen Des Natürlichen Systems, der Vergleichenden Anatomie und der Phylogenetic. Theoretische Morphologie und Systematik. 2nd edn 1956. Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft, Geest und Portig, K.-G. Leipzig

  • Richards R (2002) Kuhnian values and cladistic parsimony. Perspect Sci 10:1–27. doi:10.1162/106361402762674780

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards R (2003) Character individuation in phylogenetic inference. Philos Sci 70:264–279. doi:10.1086/375467

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richter S (2005) Homologies in phylogenetic analyses–concepts and tests. Theory Biosci 124:105–120

    Google Scholar 

  • Riedl R (1978) Order in living organisms: a systems analysis of evolution. Wiley, Chichester (trans. 1975. Die Ordnung Des Lebendigen. München: Paul Parey.)

  • Rieppel O (1988) Fundamentals of comparative biology. Birkhauser Verlag AG, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (1994) Homology, topology, and typology: the history of modern debates. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. The hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 63–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2004) The language of systematics, and the philosophy of ‘total evidence’. Syst Biodivers 2:9–19. doi:10.1017/S147720000400132X

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2005) Modules, kinds, and homology. J Exp Zool (Mol Dev Evol) 304B:18–27. doi:10.1002/jez.b.21025

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2006a) Willi Hennig on transformation series: metaphysics and epistemology. Taxon 55:377–385

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2006b) The merits of similarity reconsidered. Syst Biodivers 4:137–147. doi:10.1017/S1477200005001830

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2008a) Origins, taxa, names and meanings. Cladistics 24:598–610. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.2007.00195.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2008) ‘Total evidence’ in phylogenetic systematics. Biol Philos (accepted)

  • Rieppel O Species, monophyly, cladistics, phylogeography, metaphysics. Synthese (submitted)

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2001) The origin of snakes: limits of a scientific debate. Biologist 48:110–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2002) Similarity. Biol J Linn Soc Lond 75:59–82. doi:10.1046/j.1095-8312.2002.00006.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2007) The poverty of taxonomic characters. Biol Philos 22:95–113. doi:10.1007/s10539-006-9024-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanderson MJ, Donoghue MJ (1996) The relationship between homoplasy and confidence in a phylogenetic tree. In: Sanderson MJ, Hufford L (eds) Homoplasy. The recurrence of similarity in evolution. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 67–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuh RT (1999) Biological systematics: principles and applications. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Scotland RW, Olmstead RG, Bennett JR (2003) Phylogeny reconstruction: the role of morphology. Syst Biol 52:539–548

    Google Scholar 

  • Sereno PC (2007) Logical basis for morphological characters in phylogenetics. Cladistics 23:565–587

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith ND, Turner AH (2005) Morphology’s role in phylogeny reconstruction: perspectives from paleontology. Syst Biol 54:166–173. doi:10.1080/10635150590906000

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1983) Parsimony methods in systematics. In: Platnick NI, Funk VA (eds) Advances in cladistics, vol 2. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 37–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1988) Reconstructing the past. Parsimony, evolution, and inference. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2005) Parsimony and its presuppositions. In: Albert VA (ed) Parsimony, phylogeny, and genomics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 43–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2008) Evidence and evolution. The logic behind the science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneath PHA, Sokal RR (1973) Numerical taxonomy. The principles and practice of numerical classification. WH Freeman, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens PF (1984) Homology and phylogeny: morphology and systematics. Syst Bot 9:395–409. doi:10.2307/2418788

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevens PF (1991) Character states, morphological variation, and phylogenetic analysis: a review. Syst Bot 16:553–583. doi:10.2307/2419343

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevens PF (2000) On characters and character states: do overlapping and non-overlapping variation, morphology and molecules all yield data of the same value? In: Scotland R, Pennington RT (eds) Homology and systematics. Coding characters for phylogenetic analysis. Taylor and Francis, London, pp 81–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Thiele K (1993) The holy grail of the perfect character: the cladistic treatment of morphometric data. Cladistics 9:275–304. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.1993.tb00226.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Syoc RJ, Winther RG (1999) Sponge-inhabiting barnacles of the Americas: a new species of Acasta (Cirripedia, Archaeobalanidae), first record from the eastern Pacific, including discussion of the evolution of cirral morphology. Crustaceana 72:467–486. doi:10.1163/156854099503528

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vergara-Silva F Pattern cladistics and the realism—antirealism debate in the philosophy of biology (This issue)

  • Wägele K (2004) Hennig’s phylogenetic systematics brought up to date. In: Williams DM, Forey PL (eds) Milestones in systematics. CRC Press, Boca Raton, pp 101–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1994) Homology and the mechanisms of development. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. The hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 273–299

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1996) Homologues, natural kinds and the evolution of modularity. Am Zool 36:36–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (ed) (2001) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley EO (1981) Phylogenetics. The theory and practice of phylogenetic systematics. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley EO, Siegel-Causey D, Brooks DR, Funk VA (1991) The compleat cladist. A primer of phylogenetic procedures. University of Kansas Museum of Natural History

  • Williams DM, Ebach MC (2007) Foundations of Systematics and Biogeography. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams DM, Scotland RW, Humphries CJ, Siebert DJ (1996) Confusion in philosophy: a comment on Williams. Synthese 108:127–136. doi:10.1007/BF00414008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams DM, Siebert DJ (2000) Characters, homology and three-item analysis. In: Scotland R, Pennington RT (eds) Homology and systematics. Coding characters for phylogenetic analysis. Taylor and Francis, London, pp 183–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams P (1992) Confusion in cladism. Synthese 91:135–152. doi:10.1007/BF00484973

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RA (ed) (1999) Species: new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2001) Varieties of modules: kinds, levels, origins and behaviors. J Exp Zool B (Mol Dev Evol) 291:116–129. doi:10.1002/jez.1064

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2006a) Fisherian and Wrightian perspectives in evolutionary genetics and model-mediated imposition of theoretical assumptions. J Theor Biol 240:218–232. doi:10.1016/j.jtbi.2005.09.010

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2006b) On the dangers of making scientific models ontologically independent: taking Richard Levins’ warnings seriously. Biol Philos 21:703–724. doi:10.1007/s10539-006-9053-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2006c) Parts and theories in compositional biology. Biol Philos 21:471–499. doi:10.1007/s10539-005-9002-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2008) Systemic Darwinism. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 105(33):11833–11838. doi:10.1073/pnas.0711445105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woese CR (2000) Interpreting the universal phylogenetic tree. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 97:8392–8396. doi:10.1073/pnas.97.15.8392

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper emerged from multiple conversations with Olivier Rieppel. I am also grateful to Niels Bonde, Kirk Fitzhugh, David Hull, Fabrizzio McManus Guerrero, Brent Mishler, Elliot Sober, Peter Stevens, Francisco Vergara-Silva, and David M Williams for discussion and comments on an earlier draft. Springer Science and Business Media (Fig. 1), John Wiley & Sons, Inc. (Figs. 2 and 3), and University of Chicago Press (Fig. 4) kindly granted permission to reproduce original material.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rasmus Grønfeldt Winther.

Additional information

An erratum to this article can be found at http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10441-009-9074-0

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Winther, R.G. Character Analysis in Cladistics: Abstraction, Reification, and the Search for Objectivity. Acta Biotheor 57, 129–162 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-008-9064-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-008-9064-7

Keywords

Navigation