Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Predictive brains, dreaming selves, sleeping bodies: how the analysis of dream movement can inform a theory of self- and world-simulation in dreams

  • S.I. : Predictive Brains
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I discuss the relationship between bodily experiences in dreams and the sleeping, physical body. I question the popular view that dreaming is a naturally and frequently occurring real-world example of cranial envatment. This view states that dreams are functionally disembodied states: in a majority of dreams, phenomenal experience, including the phenomenology of embodied selfhood, unfolds completely independently of external and peripheral stimuli and outward movement. I advance an alternative and more empirically plausible view of dreams as weakly phenomenally-functionally embodied states. The view predicts that bodily experiences in dreams can be placed on a continuum with bodily illusions in wakefulness. It also acknowledges that there is a high degree of variation across dreams and different sleep stages in the degree of causal coupling between dream imagery, sensory input, and outward motor activity. Furthermore, I use the example of movement sensations in dreams and their relation to outward muscular activity to develop a predictive processing account. I propose that movement sensations in dreams are associated with a basic and developmentally early kind of bodily self-sampling. This account, which affords a central role to active inference, can then be broadened to explain other aspects of self- and world-simulation in dreams. Dreams are world-simulations centered on the self, and important aspects of both self- and world-simulation in dreams are closely linked to bodily self-sampling, including muscular activity, illusory own-body perception, and vestibular orienting in sleep. This is consistent with cognitive accounts of dream generation, in which long-term beliefs and expectations, as well as waking concerns and memories play an important role. What I add to this picture is an emphasis on the real-body basis of dream imagery. This offers a novel perspective on the formation of dream imagery and suggests new lines of research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Specifically, Bradley argues that to explain the failure of outward movement, it is not enough to appeal to a general weakness of ideas in dreams—dream imagery and emotions are, he notes, often quite intense. Instead, Bradley thinks the problem lies in a vagueness that is specific to ideas of movement. Motor ideas often remain indeterminate in dreams, and their lack of specificity results from our inability, in standard cases, to perceive the position of our actual limbs in sleep. Without the detail that is grounded in own-body perception, the ideas of movement in dreams are too vague to cause movement in the sleeping body. Thus there is, for Bradley, a complex story to be told about the relationship between dream imagery, the way we experience our physical bodies in sleep, and outward motor activity.

  2. Note that the distinction between the two types of embodiment is already implicit in Bradley’s (1894) discussion of the problem of dream movement. Dream movements illustrate the distinction quite clearly, because they often appear to contrast starkly with seeming inertia of the sleeping body (as in dreams of flying or falling while lying still in bed).

  3. A problem that immediately comes to mind is that the phenomenological equivalence claim leaves open what exactly the phenomenological profile of waking bodily experience is supposed to be.

  4. As a further example, consider the example of flying in dreams. While examples of dream flying may be loosely modeled on swimming or observed flight in birds, the experience of unsupported flying has no straightforward waking model. Yet, flying dreams are striking for their high degree of subjective realism and vividness (Windt 2015a, p. 454f); during the dream, they seem completely convincing. Here, I am proposing that to explain this seemingly realistic quality, we need not appeal to rich phenomenal embodiment or phenomenological equivalence.

  5. Another way to extend this research is to consider cases in which spatiotemporal self-location as the crucial structural feature of dreaming is lost. A precise concept of dreaming as defined, minimally, by its immersive, here-and-now structure can be used to develop a precise framework for describing different kinds of dreamless sleep experience (Windt 2015b; Windt et al. 2016). This framework can then guide the investigation of transitions between nonconscious sleep and more complex kinds of dreamless and dreamful experience.

  6. There may also be variation both between and within sleep stages. It is common to distinguish between phasic and tonic REM sleep, where the former is associated with bursts of rapid eye movements (see Ermis et al. 2010 for discussion and further references). Arousal thresholds are different for the two substages, suggesting that phasic REM sleep is a state of heightened seclusion from the environment, whereas tonic REM sleep is characterized by higher sensitivity to external stimuli (Ermis et al. 2010). In an fMRI study investigating thalamocortical reactivity to auditory stimulation during REM sleep, Wehrle et al. (2007) found different patterns of reactivity during tonic and phasic REM sleep: tonic REM sleep was associated with residual activation of the auditory cortex, suggesting that some processing of external stimuli was preserved. By contrast, phasic REM periods were associated with heightened activity of a thalamocortical network that appeared to be functioning as an isolated and closed intrinsic loop. Throughout sleep and even within REM sleep, we thus appear to cycle between periods of heightened responsiveness to external stimuli and periods of stronger environmental seclusion, which are carefully orchestrated by spontaneous fluctuations in brain activity. There is also some evidence for differences in dream imagery, with visual imagery being rated as clearer and more vivid following awakenings from phasic (as compared to tonic) REM sleep (Rechtschaffen and Buchignani 1983). However, other studies failed to find differences in dream imagery between the two substages (Hodoba et al. 2008).

  7. This contradicts the standard view that NREM parasomnias are examples of unconscious automatisms—essentially zombie-like behaviors occurring in the absence of phenomenal experience. See Revonsuo (2006) and Windt et al. (2016) for discussion.

  8. This is why Freudian dream theory, which emphasized the psychic sources of dreaming, was strongly opposed to this view.

  9. Again, my proposal that dreams are weakly phenomenally-functionally embodied states does not bring with it any metaphysical commitments. Here, I am interested only in the causally enabling conditions for certain types of dream experience but don’t make any strong claims about the constitutive supervenience base of dreaming.

  10. This dichotomous treatment of the sensory input and motor output blockades corresponds to the classical distinction between perception and action. In this conception, perception is conceived of as a largely passive, receptive process of synthesizing incoming, bottom-up stimuli into a coherent image of the world. By contrast, action is viewed as involving intentional, top-down control of body movements. This classical perception-action dichotomy is now rejected by leading theories in cognitive neuroscience and philosophy as oversimplified and outdated (see Hohwy 2013, chap. 4). I return to this issue in Sect. 5.1.

  11. Considering these cases, we can ask, what is the required degree of correspondence between outward behavior and dream experience for an episode to count as dream enactment behavior? In cases where body movements bear no obvious relation to dream content, it seems more apt to speak of dream-associated behaviors. For example, in nightmares associated with indiscriminate leg movements or tossing and turning, motor activity seems only loosely associated with dream experience but lacks any direct and easily identifiable correspondence to specific dream contents. For dream enactment behavior, a tighter link between experienced and outward movement seems required.

  12. Note that if the cranial envatment view fails and dreams are not functionally disembodied, but weakly phenomenally-functionally embodied states, then it might not be quite correct say that prediction errors fail to be processed in dreams. At least a subgroup of dreams may involve higher-level models attempting to make sense of prediction errors. If dream bizarreness and instability are indeed a result of attenuated processing of prediction error signals, then we might also expect varying levels of bizarreness in dreams to be associated with the varying degrees to which prediction error signals continue to be processed in sleep. I do not want to speculate more on this issue here, but only to point out that this would fit in nicely with the fact that bizarreness seems to be unevenly distributed over different types of dreams (Domhoff 2007).

  13. In one study, participants whose eyes had been taped open were presented with illuminated objects such as books and coffee pots during REM sleep (Rechtschaffen and Foulkes 1965). Independent judges were able to match the presented objects to the dream reports only at chance level, and there was not a single unambiguous case of incorporation. There is some evidence that light cues can be incorporated in dreams, and this is sometimes suggested as a method for the induction of lucid dreaming (see Stumbrys et al. 2012 for discussion and further references). But even such cases of clear incorporation of visual stimuli are limited in their ability to explain specific contents of dreaming.

  14. For an insightful discussion of imagining and perceiving from this perspective, see Kirchhoff (2017).

  15. More recently, the debate between internalist and externalist-friendly predictive processing accounts has moved on to more specific issues. Both Hohwy and Clark agree that predictive processing emphasizes the importance of internal models—their disagreement hinges on whether these models are rich (Hohwy in press) or sparse, involving “computationally frugal, but more behaviourally interactive” (Clark 2016, p. 11f) solutions that carry less “reconstructive baggage” (Clark 2016, p. 10); whether the boundary between internal models and the worldly causes they predict is strict and immutable, with cognitive processing occurring “wholly behind a sensory veil, segregated from the world” (Hohwy 2016, p. 120); whether there is genuine or merely causal continuity between the environment and the brain (Hohwy 2013, p. 239); and whether the process of prediction error minimization involves hypothesis testing in any literal sense (Clark 2016). According to Hohwy (2013, p. 228), the right response to questions on the evidentiary seclusion versus openness of perception is to not force a choice,

    but try to reconceive the perceptual relation to the world such that we do not have to choose between perception being ‘direct’ or ‘indirect’ in the first place. Instead, we should be able to retain the grain of truth in both sides of the debate.

    Here, I will leave these issues to the side, as I am more interested in a more basic point. Where the internalist, emphasizing the seclusion of the brain, might construe perception as an instance of online hallucination or online dreaming, the externalist will claim that dreaming is a form of offline perception, phenomenologically different from waking because the characteristic openness to the world has been temporarily lost (Clark 2015, p. 196). My main point is that both sides mischaracterize the functional relation between dreaming and the body—or at least have not given it the theoretical attention it deserves.

  16. This idea nicely complements Blumberg’s own proposal. To elucidate the developmental role of twitching, he uses an example that is similar to Dennett’s robot control room thought experiment (Blumberg 2015; Blumberg et al. 2013b). In it, we are asked to imagine being

    imprisoned in the control room of a giant robot. Each light, when it turns on, provides rich and relevant information about the robot’s circumstances; these lights are all outputs from highly sophisticated neural net analyzers of the raw inputs streaming from the robot’s high-definition video eyes and microphone ears, touch sensors, and olfactory sensors. The buttons initiate robotic actions, all coordinated and ready to execute. (Dennett 2013, p. 102)

    To figure out which switches initiate which actions, it would be necessary to sample them in a systematic and highly selective manner, rather than by randomly throwing different switches or even turning all of them on and off simultaneously. According to Blumberg (2015), this type of selective sampling corresponds to the spatiotemporally organized character of twitching in sleep.

    For the sampling process to be efficient, the formation and optimization of internal models or testable hypotheses is crucial; clearly, what is needed is a theory-guided kind of sampling. And ideally, these models will not just be fitted to the input—the lights turning on and off—but to control the robot and use it to interact with the world, a stable body model will be needed. The system will have to figure out, in other words, which lights indicate worldly changes, and which ones indicate own-body movement. Again, bodily self-sampling is a condition for active inference: in bodily interaction with the world, the system is not only aiming to achieve a better fit of environmental stimuli to existing world models, but also continuously optimizing its own body model.

    Bodily self-sampling in sleep may also be crucial for acquiring the ability to mentally simulate motor actions in wakefulness by taking them partially offline. Such internally generated action sequences may play an important role in memory consolidation, but also in future planning. See Pezzulo (2017).

  17. Though I have not offered a detailed discussion of this here, it is instructive to consider that in wakefulness, interoceptive predictions are thought to be closely linked to the experience of presence (Seth 2013). Not much is known about interoception in dreams, but this is another area in which we might expect continued own-body perception to modulate dream experience. This is particularly promising as interoception may be closely linked to emotions (Seth 2013), and emotions play a central role in the phenomenology of dreaming (Sikka et al. 2014). See Windt (2015a, p. 370ff) for a discussion of dream emotions in relation to weak functional embodiment; for a discussion of interoception and emotion in dreams from the perspective of predictive processing, see Bucci and Grasso (2017).

  18. One aspect of this account will be to make sense of the association between dreams and spontaneous thoughts, daydreams, and waking imagination. Based on neurophysiological and phenomenological similarities, it has been suggested that dreaming is closely related to spontaneous thought and mind wandering during wakefulness and that both are expressions of the same cognitive processes (Fox et al. 2013).

  19. Certain cases of heautoscopy, in which the sense of self-location either alternates between a visual double and the physical body or the subject feels simultaneously located in both, may be an exception (Blanke and Mohr 2005). But as one would expect, such cases of bilocation (Furlanetto et al. 2013) and simultaneous identification with two body models appear to be rare.

  20. Tellingly, Wiese (2016) discusses attenuation for the sensory consequences of self-generated movements, as in self-tickling, to propose that systematic but evolutionarily beneficial misrepresentation plays a central role in predictive processing accounts of movement and action generation. More generally, attenuation of self-generated stimuli plays an important role in predictive processing accounts: to enable action, we need to attend away from our current bodily state. For example, when intending to move, proprioceptive prediction errors need to be suppressed and the expected precision of ascending sensory prediction errors from lower to higher levels needs to be attenuated. An intriguing observation is that this process may be closely related to the phenomenology of bodily action in standard wakefulness. In a recent publication, Limanowski (2017, p. 5) writes, that “to be able to interact with the world, I need to withdraw attention from my body’s current state and focus it on what I predict sensing in my desired state. This conclusion is very similar to that of classical phenomenology, namely, that the ‘experiential absence’ of the body is necessary for action in the world—being a lived body-environment—and that attention directed towards the objective body is detrimental to normal performance.” It might also explain why sometimes, attention can disrupt performance.

References

  • Adler, S. R. (2011). Sleep paralysis: Night-mares, nocebos, and the mind-body connection. New Brunswick, New Jersey & London: Rutgers University Press.

  • Alessandria, M., Vetrugno, R., Cortelli, P., & Montagna, P. (2011). Normal body scheme and absent phantom limb experience in amputees while dreaming. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(4), 1831–1834.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apps, M. A., & Tsakiris, M. (2014). The free-energy self: A predictive coding account of self-recognition. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 41, 85–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arkin, A. M., Toth, M. F., Baker, J., & Hastey, J. M. (1970). The degree of concordance between the content of sleep talking and mentation recalled in wakefulness. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 151(6), 375–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnold-Forster, M. (1921). Studies in dreams. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arzy, S., Seeck, M., Ortigue, S., Spinelli, L., & Blanke, O. (2006). Induction of an illusory shadow person. Nature, 443(7109), 287–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore, S. (1988). A theory of lucid dreams and OBEs. In J. Gackenbach & S. LaBerge (Eds.), Conscious mind, sleeping brain: Perspectives on lucid dreaming (pp. 373–387). New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blagrove, M., Blakemore, S.-J., & Thayer, B. R. (2006). The ability to self-tickle following Rapid eye movement sleep dreaming. Consciousness and Cognition, 15(2), 285–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Smith, J., Steel, R., Johnstone, E., & Frith, C. D. (2000). The perception of self-produced sensory stimuli in patients with auditory hallucinations and passivity experiences: Evidence for a breakdown in self-monitoring. Psychological Medicine, 30(05), 1131–1139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, O., & Metzinger, T. (2009). Full-body illusions and minimal phenomenal selfhood. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(1), 7–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, O., & Mohr, C. (2005). Out-of-body experience, heautoscopy, and autoscopic hallucination of neurological origin: Implications for neurocognitive mechanisms of corporeal awareness and self-consciousness. Brain Research Reviews, 50(1), 184–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2005). Action in perception by Alva Noë. The Journal of Philosophy, 102, 259–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, M. S. (2010). Beyond dreams: Do sleep-related movements contribute to brain development? Frontiers in Neurology, 1, 140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, M. S. (2015). Developing sensorimotor systems in our sleep. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 24(1), 32–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, M. S., & Plumeau, A. M. (2016). A new view of “dream enactment” in REM sleep behavior disorder. Sleep Medicine Reviews, 30, 34–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, M. S., Coleman, C. M., Gerth, A. I., & McMurray, B. (2013). Spatiotemporal structure of REM sleep twitching reveals developmental origins of motor synergies. Current Biology, 23(21), 2100–2109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, M. S., Marques, H. G., & Iida, F. (2013). Twitching in sensorimotor development from sleeping rats to robots. Current Biology, 23(12), R532–R537.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boeve, B. F. (2010). REM sleep behavior disorder: Updated review of the core features, the RBD-neurodegenerative disease association, evolving concepts, controversies, and future directions. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1184, 15–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botvinick, M., & Cohen, J. (1998). Rubber hands ’feel’ touch that eyes see. Nature, 391(6669), 756–756.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, F. (1894). On the failure of movement in dream. Mind, 3(11), 373–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brugger, P. (2006). From phantom limb to phantom body: Varieties of extracorporeal awareness. In G. Knoblich, I. M. Thornton, M. Grosjean, & M. Shiffrar (Eds.), Human body perception from the inside out. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brugger, P. (2008). The phantom limb in dreams. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(4), 1272–1278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bucci, A., & Grasso, M. (2017). Sleep and dreaming in the predictive processing framework. In T. K. Metzinger & W. Wiese (Eds.), Philosophy and predictive processing. Frankfurt: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, J. A. (2003). Sleep paralysis and the structure of waking-nightmare hallucinations. Dreaming, 13(3), 163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, J. A. (2005). Sleep paralysis episode frequency and number, types, and structure of associated hallucinations. Journal of Sleep Research, 14(3), 319–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, J. A., & Girard, T. A. (2007a). Paranoid delusions and threatening hallucinations: A prospective study of sleep paralysis experiences. Consciousness and Cognition, 16(4), 959–974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, J. A., & Girard, T. A. (2007b). The nature and varieties of felt presence experiences: A reply to Nielsen. Consciousness and Cognition, 16(4), 984–991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, J. A., & Girard, T. A. (2009). The body unbound: Vestibular-motor hallucinations and out-of-body experiences. Cortex, 45(2), 201–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, J. A., Rueffer, S. D., & Newby-Clark, I. R. (1999). Hypnagogic and hypnopompic hallucinations during sleep paralysis: Neurological and cultural construction of the night-mare. Consciousness and Cognition, 8(3), 319–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicogna, P., & Bosinelli, M. (2001). Consciousness during dreams. Consciousness and Cognition, 10(1), 26–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2012). Dreaming the whole cat: Generative models, predictive processing, and the enactivist conception of perceptual experience. Mind, 121(483), 753–771.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(03), 181–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Nous,. doi:10.1111/nous.12140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dement, W., & Kleitman, N. (1957). The relation of eye movements during sleep to dream activity: An objective method for the study of dreaming. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 53(5), 339–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dement, W., & Wolpert, E. A. (1958). The relation of eye movements, body motility, and external stimuli to dream content. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 55(6), 543.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2013). Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1641/2013). René descartes: Meditations on first philosophy: With selections from the objections and replies. In J. Cottingham (Ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Desseilles, M., Dang-Vu, T. T., Sterpenich, V., & Schwartz, S. (2011). Cognitive and emotional processes during dreaming: A neuroimaging view. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(4), 998–1008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Domhoff, G. W. (2007). Realistic simulation and bizarreness in dream content: Past findings and suggestions for future research. In D. Barrett & P. McNamara (Eds.), The new science of dreaming: Content, recall, and personality characteristics (Vol. 2, pp. 1–27). Westport, CT: Praeger Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Domhoff, G. W. (2013). Finding meaning in dreams: A quantitative approach. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doneshka, P., & Kehaiyov, A. (1977). Some peculiarities of the dreams of patients with vestibular diseases. Acta Medica Iugoslavica, 32(1), 45–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dresler, M., Koch, S. P., Wehrle, R., Spoormaker, V. I., Holsboer, F., Steiger, A., et al. (2011). Dreamed movement elicits activation in the sensorimotor cortex. Current Biology, 21(21), 1833–1837.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erlacher, D., Schädlich, M., Stumbrys, T., & Schredl, M. (2014). Time for actions in lucid dreams: Effects of task modality, length, and complexity. Frontiers in psychology, 4, 1013.

  • Ermis, U., Krakow, K., & Voss, U. (2010). Arousal thresholds during human tonic and phasic REM sleep. Journal of Sleep Research, 19(3), 400–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenwick, P., Schatzman, M., Worsley, A., Adams, J., Stone, S., & Baker, A. (1984). Lucid dreaming: Correspondence between dreamed and actual events in one subject during REM sleep. Biological Psychology, 18(4), 243–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez-Arcos, A., Iranzo, A., Serradell, M., Gaig, C., & Santamaria, J. (2015). The clinical phenotype of idiopathic Rapid eye movement sleep behavior disorder at presentation: A study in 203 consecutive patients. Sleep, 39(1), 121–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, P. C., & Frith, C. D. (2009). Perceiving is believing: A Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(1), 48–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, K. C. R., Nijeboer, S., Solomonova, E., Domhoff, G. W., & Christoff, K. (2013). Dreaming as mind wandering: Evidence from functional neuroimaging and first-person content reports. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7.

  • Frank, B., & Lorenzoni, E. (1989). Experiences of phantom limb sensations in dreams. Psychopathology, 22(4), 182–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., Adams, R., Perrinet, L., & Breakspear, M. (2012). Perceptions as hypotheses: Saccades as experiments. Frontiers in Psychology, 3, 151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furlanetto, T., Bertone, C., & Becchio, C. (2013). The bilocated mind: New perspectives on self-localization and self-identification. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7, 71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, R, Jr., Grossman, W. I., Roffwarg, H. P., & Weiner, H. (1975). The relationship of small limb movements during REM sleep to dreamed limb action. Psychosomatic Medicine, 37(2), 147–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Germain, A., & Nielsen, T. A. (2003). Sleep pathophysiology in posttraumatic stress disorder and idiopathic nightmare sufferers. Biological Psychiatry, 54(10), 1092–1098.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilestro, G. F., Tononi, G., & Cirelli, C. (2009). Widespread changes in synaptic markers as a function of sleep and wakefulness in Drosophila. Science, 324(5923), 109–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. V. (1866). Concerning the perceptions in general. In Treatise on physiological optics (Vol. III, 3rd edn., J. P. C. Southall, Trans. 1925 Opt. Soc. Am. Section 26, reprinted New York: Dover, 1962).

  • Herlin, B., Leu-Semenescu, S., Chaumereuil, C., & Arnulf, I. (2015). Evidence that non-dreamers do dream: A REM sleep behaviour disorder model. Journal of Sleep Research, 24(6), 602–609.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herman, J. (2000). Reflexive and orienting properties of REM sleep dreaming and eye movements. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(6), 950.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirscher, V., Unbehaun, T., Feige, B., Nissen, C., Riemann, D., & Spiegelhalder, K. (2015). Patients with primary insomnia in the sleep laboratory: Do they present with typical nights of sleep? Journal of Sleep Research, 24(4), 383–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A. (1988). The dreaming brain. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A. (2009). REM sleep and dreaming: Towards a theory of protoconsciousness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(11), 803–813.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A., & Friston, K. J. (2012). Waking and dreaming consciousness: Neurobiological and functional considerations. Progress in Neurobiology, 98(1), 82–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A., & Friston, K. J. (2014). Consciousness, dreams, and inference: The cartesian theatre revisited. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 21(1–2), 6–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A., Pace-Schott, E. F., & Stickgold, R. (2000). Dreaming and the brain: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of conscious states. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(6), 793–842. (discussion 904–1121) .

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodoba, D., Hrabric, K., Krmpotic, P., & Kujundzic-Tiljak, M. (2008). Dream recall after night awakenings from tonic/phasic REM sleep. Collegium Antropologicum, 32(Supplement 1), 69–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoff, H. (1929). Zusammenhang von Vestibulärfunktion, Schlafstellung und Traumleben. European Neurology, 71(5–6), 366–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoff, H., & Pötzl, O. (1937). Über die labyrinthären Beziehungen von Flugsensationen und Flugträumen. European Neurology, 97(4), 193–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2014). The neural organ explains the mind Open MIND: Open MIND. Frankfurt: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2015). The diversity of bayesian explanation. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 19(T). Frankfurt: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2016). Prediction, agency and body ownership. (2016). In A. K. Engel, K. J. Friston, & D. Kragic (Eds.), The Pragmatic turn: Toward action-oriented views in cognitive science, Strüngmann forum reports, vol. 18, J. Lupp, series editor. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Hohwy, J. (in press). The predictive processing theory and 4e cognition. In A. Newen, L. Bruin, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of cognition: embodied, embedded, enactive and extended. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hohwy, J., & Michael, J. (in press). Why should any body have a self? In F. de Vignemont & A. Alsmith (Eds.), The body and the self, revisited. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.

  • Hong, C. C. H., Harris, J. C., Pearlson, G. D., Kim, J. S., Calhoun, V. D., Fallon, J. H., et al. (2009). fMRI evidence for multisensory recruitment associated with rapid eye movements during sleep. Human Brain Mapping, 30(5), 1705–1722.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honma, M., Plass, J., Brang, D., Florczak, S. M., Grabowecky, M., & Paller, K. A. (2016). Sleeping on the rubber-hand illusion: Memory reactivation during sleep facilitates multisensory recalibration. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2016(1), 1–10.

  • Honma, M., Yoshiike, T., Ikeda, H., Kim, Y., & Kuriyama, K. (2014). Sleep dissolves illusion: Sleep withstands learning of visuo-tactile-proprioceptive integration induced by repeated days of rubber hand illusion training. PLOS ONE, 9(1), e85734.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, M. J., & Schenck, C. H. (2015). REM sleep behavior disorder. In Disorders of sleep and circadian rhythms in Parkinson’s Disease (pp. 131–144). Springer.

  • Jezower, I. (1928/1985). Das Buch der Träume. Frankfurt: Ullstein.

  • Kahn, D., Stickgold, R., Pace-Schott, E., & Hobson, J. (2000). Dreaming and waking consciousness: A character recognition study. Journal of Sleep Research, 9(4), 317–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaliuzhna, M., Vibert, D., Grivaz, P., & Blanke, O. (2015). Out-of-body experiences and other complex dissociation experiences in a patient with unilateral peripheral vestibular damage and deficient multisensory integration. Multisensory Research, 28(5–6), 613–635.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2017). Predictive processing, perceiving and imagining: Is to perceive to imagine, or something close to it? Philosophical Studies, Online first, pp. 1–17.

  • LaBerge, S. (1985). Lucid dreaming: The power of being awake and aware in your dreams. Los Angeles: Jeremy P. Tarcher.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge, S. P., Nagel, L. E., Dement, W. C., & Zarcone, V. P. (1981). Lucid dreaming verified by volitional communication during REM sleep. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 52, 727–732.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge, S., & DeGracia, D. J. (2000). Varieties of lucid dreaming experience. Individual Differences in Conscious Experience, 20, 269.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leclair-Visonneau, L., Oudiette, D., Gaymard, B., Leu-Semenescu, S., & Arnulf, I. (2010). Do the eyes scan dream images during rapid eye movement sleep? Evidence from the rapid eye movement sleep behaviour disorder model. Brain, 133(6), 1737–1746.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenggenhager, B., & Lopez, C. (2015). Vestibular contributions to the sense of body, self, and others. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 23(T). Frankfurt: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenggenhager, B., Lopez, C., & Blanke, O. (2008). Influence of galvanic vestibular stimulation on egocentric and object-based mental transformations. Experimental Brain Research, 184(2), 211–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenggenhager, B., Tadi, T., Metzinger, T., & Blanke, O. (2007). Video ergo sum: Manipulating bodily self-consciousness. Science, 317(5841), 1096–1099.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, K., & Ogilvie, R. (1996). Vestibular dreams: The effect of rocking on dream mentation. Dreaming, 6(1), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Limanowski, J., & Blankenburg, F. (2013). Minimal self-models and the free energy principle. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7, 547.

    Google Scholar 

  • Limanowski, J. (2017). (Dis-)Attending to the body. In T. K. Metzinger & W. Wiese (Eds.), Philosophy and predictive processing. Frankfurt: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Llinás, R. R., & Paré, D. (1991). Of dreaming and wakefulness. Neuroscience, 44(3), 521–535.

    Google Scholar 

  • Llinás, R., & Ribary, U. (1994). Perception as an oneiric-like state modulated by the senses. In C. Koch & J. Davis (Eds.), Large-scale neuronal theories of the brain (pp. 111–124). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopez, C., Halje, P., & Blanke, O. (2008). Body ownership and embodiment: Vestibular and multisensory mechanisms. Neurophysiologie Clinique/Clinical Neurophysiology, 38(3), 149–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1919). Die Analyse der Empfindungen und das Verhältnis des Psychischen zum Physischen. Jena: Verlag von Gustav Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macnish, R. (1838). The philosophy of sleep. Glasgow: WR M’Phun.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madary, M. (2015). Extending the explanandum for predictive processing: A commentary on Andy Clark. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 7(C). Frankfurt: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mavromatis, A. (1987). Hypnagogia: The unique state of consciousness between wakefulness and sleep. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNamara, P., McLaren, D., Smith, D., Brown, A., & Stickgold, R. (2005). A “Jekyll and Hyde” within aggressive versus friendly interactions in REM and non-REM dreams. Psychological Science, 16(2), 130–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2003). Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2009). The ego tunnel. The science of the soul and the myth of the self. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. K. (2013). Why are dreams interesting for philosophers? The example of minimal phenomenal selfhood, plus an agenda for future research. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 746.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulder, T., Hochstenbach, J., Dijkstra, P. U., & Geertzen, J. H. (2008). Born to adapt, but not in your dreams. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(4), 1266–1271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T. A. (1992). A self-observational study of spontaneous hypnagogic imagery using the upright napping procedure. Imagination, Cognition and Personality, 11(4), 353–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T. A. (1993). Changes in the kinesthetic content of dreams following somatosensory stimulation of leg muscles during REM sleep. Dreaming, 3(2), 99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T. A. (1995). Describing and modeling hypnagogic imagery using a systematic self-observation procedure. Dreaming, 5(2), 75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T. A. (2007). Felt presence: Paranoid delusion or hallucinatory social imagery? Consciousness and Cognition, 16(4), 975–983.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T. A. (2010). Dream analysis and classification: The reality simulation perspective. In M. Kryger, T. Roth, & W. C. Dement (Eds.), Principles and practice of sleep medicine (5th ed., pp. 595–603). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T. (2017). Microdream neurophenomenology. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 3(1), 1–17.

  • Nielsen, T. A., Zadra, A. L., Simard, V., Saucier, S., Stenstrom, P., Smith, C., et al. (2003). The typical dreams of Canadian university students. Dreaming, 13(4), 211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T., Ouellet, L., & Zadra, A. (1995). Pressure stimulation during REM sleep alters dream limb activity and body bizarreness. Sleep Research, 24, 134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T., Svob, C., & Kuiken, D. (2009). Dream-enacting behaviors in a normal population. Sleep, 32(12), 1629–1636.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge (MA): MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Occhionero, M., Cicogna, P., Natale, V., Esposito, M. J., & Bosinelli, M. (2005). Representation of self in SWS and REM dreams. Sleep and Hypnosis, 7(2), 77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oudiette, D., Leu, S., Pottier, M., Buzare, M.-A., Brion, A., & Arnulf, I. (2009). Dreamlike mentations during sleepwalking and sleep terrors in adults. Sleep, 32(12), 1621–1627.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pace-Schott, E. F. (2013). Dreaming as a story-telling instinct. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagel, J., Blagrove, M., Levin, R., Stickgold, B., & White, S. (2001). Definitions of dream: A paradigm for comparing field descriptive specific studies of dream. Dreaming, 11(4), 195.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pezzulo, G. (2017). Tracing the roots of cognition in predictive processing. In T. K. Metzinger & W. Wiese (Eds.), Philosophy and Predictive Processing. Frankfurt: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeiffer, C., Serino, A., & Blanke, O. (2014). The vestibular system: A spatial reference for bodily self-consciousness. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 8, 31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Brains in a vat. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rechtschaffen, A., & Buchignani, C. (1983). Visual dimensions and correlates of dream images. Sleep Research, 12, S189.

  • Rechtschaffen, A., & Foulkes, D. (1965). Effect of visual stimuli on dream content. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 20(3 supplement), 1149–1160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo, A. (2005). The self in dreams. In T. E. Feinberg & J. P. Keenan (Eds.), The lost self: Pathologies of the brain and identity (pp. 206–219). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo, A. (2006). Inner presence: Consciousness as a biological phenomenon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo, A., & Salmivalli, C. (1995). A content analysis of bizarre elements in dreams. Dreaming, 5(3), 169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo, A., Tuominen, J., & Valli, K. (2015). The avatars in the machine: Dreaming as a simulation of social reality. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 32(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saurat, M.-T., Agbakou, M., Attigui, P., Golmard, J.-L., & Arnulf, I. (2011). Walking dreams in congenital and acquired paraplegia. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(4), 1425–1432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauvageau, A., Nielsen, T. A., & Montplaisir, J. (1998). Effects of somatosensory stimulation on dream content in gymnasts and control participants: Evidence of vestibulomotor adaptation in REM Sleep. Dreaming, 8(2), 125–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A. K. (2013). Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(11), 565–573.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schönhammer, R. (2005). ’Typical dreams’: Reflections of arousal. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12(4–5), 18–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schredl, M. (2006). Factors affecting the continuity between waking and dreaming: Emotional intensity and emotional tone of the waking-life event. Sleep and Hypnosis, 8(1), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schredl, M., & Erlacher, D. (2011). Dream consciousness and sleep physiology. In D. Cvetkovic & I. Cosic (Eds.), States of consciousness: Experimental insights into meditation, waking, sleep, and dreams (pp. 93–108). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwabe, L., & Blanke, O. (2008). The vestibular component in out-of-body experiences: A computational approach. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 2, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S. (2000). A historical loop of one hundred years: Similarities between 19th century and contemporary dream research. Dreaming, 10(1), 55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2007). Do you have constant tactile experience of your feet in your shoes? Or is experience limited to what’s in attention? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14(3), 5–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sikka, P., Valli, K., Virta, T., & Revonsuo, A. (2014). I know how you felt last night, or do I? Self-and external ratings of emotions in REM sleep dreams. Consciousness and Cognition, 25, 51–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Speth, J., Frenzel, C., & Voss, U. (2013). A differentiating empirical linguistic analysis of dreamer activity in reports of EEG-controlled REM-dreams and hypnagogic hallucinations. Consciousness and Cognition, 22(3), 1013–1021.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauch, I., & Meier, B. (1996). In search of dreams: Results of experimental dream research. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumbrys, T., Erlacher, D., Schädlich, M., & Schredl, M. (2012). Induction of lucid dreams: A systematic review of evidence. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(3), 1456–1475.

    Google Scholar 

  • Symons, D. (1993). The stuff that dreams aren’t made of: Why wake-state and dream-state sensory experiences differ. Cognition, 47(3), 181–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiriac, A., Del Rio-Bermudez, C., & Blumberg, M. S. (2014). Self-generated movements with “unexpected” sensory consequences. Current Biology, 24(18), 2136–2141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M., & Haggard, P. (2005). The rubber hand illusion revisited: Visuotactile integration and self-attribution. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 31(1), 80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valli, K., Frauscher, B., Gschliesser, V., Wolf, E., Falkenstetter, T., Schönwald, S. V., et al. (2012). Can observers link dream content to behaviours in rapid eye movement sleep behaviour disorder? A cross-sectional experimental pilot study. Journal of Sleep Research, 21(1), 21–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vetrugno, R., Arnulf, I., & Montagna, P. (2008). Disappearance of “phantom limb” and amputated arm usage during dreaming in REM sleep behaviour disorder. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 79, 481– 483.

  • Vetrugno, R., Arnulf, I., & Montagna, P. (2009). Disappearance of “phantom limb” and amputated arm usage during dreaming in REM sleep behaviour disorder. BMJ Case Reports, 2009, bcr0920080851.

  • Voss, U., & Hobson, A. (2015). What is the state-of-the-art on lucid dreaming? In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 38(T). Frankfurt: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voss, U., Schermelleh-Engel, K., Windt, J., Frenzel, C., & Hobson, A. (2013). Measuring consciousness in dreams: The lucidity and consciousness in dreams scale. Consciousness and Cognition, 22(1), 8–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voss, U., Tuin, I., Schermelleh-Engel, K., & Hobson, A. (2011). Waking and dreaming: Related but structurally independent. Dream reports of congenitally paraplegic and deaf-mute persons. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(3), 673–687.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wehrle, R., Kaufmann, C., Wetter, T. C., Holsboer, F., Auer, D. P., Pollmächer, T., et al. (2007). Functional microstates within human REM sleep: First evidence from fMRI of a thalamocortical network specific for phasic REM periods. European Journal of Neuroscience, 25(3), 863–871.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weygandt, W. (1893). Entstehung der Träume. Leipzig: Grübel & Sommerblatte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiese, W. (2016). Action is enabled by systematic misrepresentations. Erkenntnis, Online first, pp. 1–20.

  • Windt, J. M. (2010). The immersive spatiotemporal hallucination model of dreaming. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(2), 295–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Windt, J. M. (2013). Reporting dream experience: Why (not) to be skeptical about dream reports. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7, 708.

  • Windt, J. M. (2015a). Dreaming: A conceptual framework for philosophy of mind and empirical research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Windt, J. M. (2015b). Just in time-dreamless sleep experience as pure subjective temporality: A commentary on Evan Thompson. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 37(C). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Windt, J. M., Harkness, D. L., & Lenggenhager, B. (2014). Tickle me, I think I might be dreaming! Sensory attenuation, self-other distinction, and predictive processing in lucid dreams. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 717.

  • Windt, J. M., Nielsen, T., & Thompson, E. (2016). Does consciousness disappear in dreamless sleep? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(12), 871–882.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. M. (1874). Grundzüge der physiologischen psychologie. Leipzig: W. Engelman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yu, C. K.-C. (2008). Typical dreams experienced by Chinese people. Dreaming, 18(1), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zadra, A. L. (2001). Recurrent dreams: Their relation to life events. In D. Barrett (Ed.), Trauma and dreams (pp. 231–247). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank two anonymous reviewers for their extremely thorough comments and helpful suggestions. I am grateful to Melanie Rosen for some great discussions and for raising important questions about the dream body at the 2017 Pacific APA meeting in Seattle. And I would like to thank Jesse Buck for valuable comments on an earlier version of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jennifer M. Windt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Windt, J.M. Predictive brains, dreaming selves, sleeping bodies: how the analysis of dream movement can inform a theory of self- and world-simulation in dreams. Synthese 195, 2577–2625 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1525-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1525-6

Keywords

Navigation