Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-14T12:52:37.172Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mere formalities: fictional normativity and normative authority

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Daniel Wodak*
Affiliation:
Philosophy, Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University, Blacksburg, VA, USA
*
Daniel Wodak dwodak@vt.edu

Abstract

It is commonly said that some standards, such as morality, are ‘normatively authoritative’ in a way that other standards, such as etiquette, are not; standards like etiquette are said to be ‘not really normative’. Skeptics deny the very possibility of normative authority, and take claims like ‘etiquette is not really normative’ to be either empty or confused. I offer a different route to defeat skeptics about authority: instead of focusing on what makes standards like morality special, we should focus on what makes standards like etiquette ‘not really normative’. I defend a fictionalist theory on which etiquette is ‘not really normative’ in roughly the same way that Sherlock is ‘not really a detective’, and show that fictionalism about some normative standards helps us explain the possibility of normative authority.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austin, J. L. 1962. Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Derek. 2016. “The Varieties of Normativity.” In The Routledge Handbook of Metaethics, edited by McPherson, T. and Plunkett, D., 567581. Routledge.Google Scholar
Baker, Derek. Forthcoming. “Skepticism about Ought Simpliciter.” Oxford Studies in Metaethics.Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael. 1992. “Practical Reasoning and Acceptance in a Context.” Mind 101 (401 ): 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, John. 2013. Rationality Through Reasoning. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell. 10.1002/9781118609088CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, Sarah. 1999. “Appearing Respectful: The Moral Significance of Manners.” Ethics 109 (4 ): 795826.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire. 2000. “The Virtue of Civility.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (3 ): 251275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chang, Ruth. 2015. “Value Incomparability and Incommensurability.” In The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory, edited by Hirose, Iwao and Olson, Jonas, 205224. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan 1995. An Essay on Belief and Acceptance. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198236047.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, David. 1997. “The Ring of Gyges: Overridingness and The Unity of Reason.” Social Philosophy and Policy 14 (1 ): 86101. 10.1017/S0265052500001680CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, David. 2004. “Moral Naturalism and Three Grades of Normativity.” In Normativity and Naturalism, edited by Schaber, P., 745. Frankfurt: Ontos-Verlag.Google Scholar
Cuneo, Terence, and Christy, Sean. 2010. “The Myth of Moral Fictionalism.” In New Waves in Metaethics, edited by Brady, Michael, 85102. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Daly, Chris. 2008. “Fictionalism and the Attitudes.” Philosophical Studies 139: 423440. 10.1007/s11098-007-9132-xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dasgupta, Shamik. 2017. “Non-Naturalism and Normative Authority.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 117 (3 ): 297319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eklund, Matti. 2015. “Fictionalism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition), edited by Zalta, Edward N.. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/fictionalism/>Google Scholar
Enoch, David. 2011. “Reason-Giving and the Law.” In Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, edited by Green, Leslie and Leiter, Brian, 138. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finlay, Stephen. 2014. Confusion of Tongues. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199347490.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, Stephen. Forthcoming. “Defining Normativity.” In Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence, edited by Plunkett, D., Shapiro, S., and Toh, K.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 2002. “Natural Law: The Classical Tradition.” In The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, 2223. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa. 1972. “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives.” The Philosophical Review 81 (3 ): 305316. 10.2307/2184328CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, Philippa. 1977. Virtues and Vices. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Gendler, Tamar. 2000. “The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance.” The Journal of Philosophy 97 (2 ): 5581. 10.2307/2678446CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart. 1961/1994. The Concept of Law 2nd Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1982. Essays on Bentham. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hershovitz, Scott. 2015. “The End of Jurisprudence.” Yale Law Journal 124: 1160.Google Scholar
Holton, Richard. 1998. “Positivism and the Internal Point of View.” Law and Philosophy 17: 617618.Google Scholar
Joyce, Richard. 2001. The Myth of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511487101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leslie, Sarah-Jane. 2015. “Hillary Clinton is the Only Man in the Obama Administration’: Dual Character Concepts, Generics, and Gender.” Analytic Philosophy 56 (2 ): 131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Judith, and Stent, Gunther S.. 1990. “I Think; Therefore I Thank: A Philosophy of Etiquette.” The American Scholar 59 (2 ): 237254.Google Scholar
McPherson, Tristram. 2011. “Against Quietist Normative Realism.” Philosophical Studies 154 (2 ): 223240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McPherson, Tristram. Forthcoming. “Authoritatively Normative Concepts.” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics.Google Scholar
Nolan, Daniel, and O’Leary-Hawthorne, John. 1996. “Reflexive Fictionalisms.” Analysis 56: 2332. 10.1093/analys/56.1.23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ogden, C. K. 1932. Bentham’s Theory of Fictions. London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters. Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Perl, Caleb, and Schroeder, Mark. Forthcoming. “Attributing Error Without Taking a Stand.” Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
Perry, Adam. 2015. “The Internal Aspect of Social Rules.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 35 (2 ): 283300. 10.1093/ojls/gqu017CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plunkett, David and Shapiro, Scott. 2017. “Law, Morality, and Everything Else: General Jurisprudence as a Branch of Metanormative Theory.” Ethics.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2009. Between Authority and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199562688.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosati, Connie S. 1995. “Naturalism, Normativity, and the Open Question Argument.” Noûs 29 (1 ): 4670.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ridge, Michael. 2014. Impassioned Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682669.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sainsbury, R. M. 2011. “Fiction and Acceptance-Relative Truth, Belief, and Assertion.” In Truth in Fiction, edited by Lihoreau, Franck, 137152. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2007. Slaves of the Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199299508.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, Scott. 2011. Legality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Matthew. 2016. “Teleology and Normativity.” In Vol. 11 of Oxford Studies in Metaethics, edited by Shafer-Landau, R., 214240. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198784647.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, Nishi, and Velleman, David. 2005. “Doxastic Deliberation.” The Philosophical Review 144 (4 ): 497534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1984. Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stanley, Jason. 2001. “Hermeneutic Fictionalism.” In Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXV: Figurative Language, edited by French, Peter and Wettstein, Howard K., 46. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie. 1999. Fiction and Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie L. 2009. “Fictional Entities.” In A Companion to Metaphysics, edited by Kim, Jaegwon, Sosa, Ernest and Rosenkrantz, Gary, 1018. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Tiffany, Evan. 2007. “Deflationary Normative Pluralism.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (5 ): 231262. 10.1353/cjp.0.0076Google Scholar
Toh, Kevin. Forthcoming. “Law, Morality, Art, the Works.” In Law as an Artifact, edited by Burazin, Luka, Himma, Kenneth and Roversi, Corrado. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Velleman, David. 2000. The Possibility of Practical Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Walton, Kendall. 1990. Mimesis as Make-Believe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wodak, Daniel. 2017a. “Why Realists Must Reject Normative Quietism.” Philosophical Studies 174 (11 ): 27952817. 10.1007/s11098-016-0811-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wodak, Daniel. 2017b. “Expressivism and Varieties of Normativity.” In Vol. 12 of Oxford Studies in Metaethics, edited by Shafer Landau, R., 265293. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wodak, Daniel. Forthcoming. “What Does ‘Legal Obligation’ Mean?Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.Google Scholar
Woods, Jack. Forthcoming. “The Authority of Formality.” Oxford Studies in Metaethics.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar