Skip to main content
Log in

Aplasic phantoms and the mirror neuron system: An enactive, developmental perspective

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Phantom limb experiences demonstrate an unexpected degree of fragility inherent in our self-perceptions. This is perhaps most extreme when congenitally absent limbs are experienced as phantoms. Aplasic phantoms highlight fundamental questions about the physiological bases of self-experience and the ontogeny of a physical, embodied sense of the self. Some of the most intriguing of these questions concern the role of mirror neurons in supporting the development of self–other mappings and hence the emergence of phantom experiences of congenitally absent limbs. In this paper, we will examine the hypothesis that aplasic phantom limb experience is the result of an ontogenetic interplay between body schemas and mirror neuron activity and that this interplay is founded on embedding in a social context. Phantom limb experience has been associated with the persistence of subjective experience of a part of the body after deafferentation through surgical or traumatic removal. We maintain that limited association is inconsistent with the extent to which phantom limb experience is reported by aplasic individuals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We might understand this by employing the metaphor of the cell membrane whose tensegrity, or tensional integrity, is maintained by compression and pressure from each side of the membrane’s surface. Its embodied immersion has the membrane in sharp relief at the interface. Though here we might be accused of moving towards a philosophy of immanence, of the necessary balance of the constituted/constitutive forces, rather than remaining strictly within the phenomenological conception.

  2. We refer here only to the physical world of objects, but would argue that the capacity to think reflexively of oneself as a self is only possible in socially embedded agents, and these are agents which naturally possess an endogenous intersubjectivity (Gallagher 2007), that is, the practical knowledge of oneself that guides from the inside out. It is through the combination of a socially embedded self-awareness and prereflective bodily self-awareness—derived through active felt agency—that a subjective conception of ourselves by ourselves (first-person) and an intersubjective conception by others of us as persons (second-person) is entailed. It is this notion of personhood which extends the self temporally into a world of morally culpable agents and morally vulnerable patients. Thus, it is that agency is ontically and epistemically prior to self, and it is agency and reflective awareness which entails personhood as judged from a first-person (subjective), second-person (empathetic/intersubjective), and third-person (objective) perspective.

  3. For the sake of clarity, let us state simply that our definition of “social” is broad and not the one favored by, for example, some linguists and sociologists as being specific to human beings and including a set of social structures, norms, institutions, culture, language, and so on. “Social” in our sense is more broadly biological, applying to living organisms that interact in a collective coexistence. See De Jaegher and Di Paolo (2007) for an operational, enactive definition of the social which is compatible with our use of the word.

  4. Perhaps we might understand self-givenness in terms of Husserl’s concept of “eidetic intuition”: the direct givenness which “refers to the acts in which ‘objects show up in person’” (Depraz et al. 2003, p. 45) and which primarily reveals itself as a perceptual and imaginative act concerned with disclosing an essence [ibid., p.55]. Self-givenness is concerned with the revelation of the tight experiential coupling between body and ownership of the experience.

  5. Melzack et al. (1997) found that 20% of congenital aplasics in their questionnaire study to have experienced phantoms (n = 76). Saadah and Melzack (1994) report a phantom incidence of around 10% in another questionnaire study of 100 aplasics.

  6. This notion of an innate body schema challenges the earlier acquired postural model favored by, amongst others, Piaget (1962), Merleau-Ponty (1962), Wallon (1947, 1965), and Simmel (1966). In their model, the infant’s experience is entirely interoceptive with the external perceptual abilities, which mark the exteroceptive domain, only developing after a matter of months.

References

  • Botvinick, M., & Cohen, J. D. (1998). Rubber hand ‘feels’ what eyes see. Nature, 391, 756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brass, M., & Heyes, C. (2005). Imitation: Is cognitive neuroscience solving the correspondence problem? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 489–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brugger, P., Kollias, S. S., Muri, R. M., Crelier, G., Hepp-Reymond, M.-C., & Regard, M. (2000). Beyond re-membering: Phantom sensations of congenitally absent limbs. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 97(11), 6167–6172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Catmur, H., Gilmeister, H., Bird, G., Liepelt, R., Brass, M., & Heyes, C. (2008). Through the looking glass: Counter-mirror activation following incompatible sensorimotor learning. European Journal of Neuroscience, 28, 1208–1215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, M. (1953). Tactile thought, with special reference to the blind. Brain, 76, 19–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Depraz, N., Varela, F., & Vermersch, P. (2003). On becoming aware: Steps to a phenomenological pragmatics. Amsterdam: John Benjamins (Advances in Consciousness Research Series).

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Vignemont, F. (2004). The co-consciousness hypothesis. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3(1), 97–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Pellegrino, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (1992). Understanding motor events: A neurophysiological study. Experimental Brain Research, 91, 176–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fadiga, L., & Craighero, L. (2007). On electrophysiological data on mirror neurons and motor representations. In S. Bråten (Ed.), On being moved: From mirror neurons to empathy. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2006) “Perceiving others in action/La perception d’autrui en action”, Fondements cognitifs del’interaction avec autrui, Collége de France (22 February 2006).

  • Gallagher, S. (2007). Moral agency, self-consciousness, and practical wisdom. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14(5–6), 199–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Meltzoff, A. (1996). The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau Ponty and recent developmental studies. Philosophical Psychology, 9(2), 211–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2005). ‘Being like me’: Self–other identity, mirror neurons and empathy. In S. Hurley & N. Chater (Eds.), Perspectives on imitation I (pp. 101–118). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzola, V., van der Worp, H., Mulder, T., Wicker, B., Rizzolatti, G., & Keysers, K. (2007). Aplasics born without hands mirror the goal of hand actions with their feet. Current Biology, 17(14), 1235–1240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Georgieff, N., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Beyond consciousness of external events: A ‘Who’ system for consciousness of action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 7, 465–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, M. (1963). L’Essence de la manifestation/The essence of manifestation. The Hague: Nijhoff. 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2001). Causes and consequences of imitation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 253–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (2005). Active perception and perceiving action: The shared circuits model. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M., & Pacherie, E. (2004). Agency, simulation, and self-identification. Mind and Language, 19(2), 113–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keysers, C., & Perrett, D. I. (2004). Demystifying social cognition: A Hebbian perspective. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 501–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kinsbourne, M., & Lempert, H. (1980). Human Figure representation by blind children. The Journal of General Psychology, 102, 33–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2006). The bodily self: The sensori-motor roots of pre-reflexive self-consciousness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 5, 89–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melzack, R., Israel, R., Lacroix, R., & Schultz, G. (1997). Phantom limbs in people with congenital deficiency or amputation in early childhood. Brain, 120, 1603–1620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception. New York: The Humanities Press. Trans. Colin Smith, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2003a). Phenomenal transparency and cognitive self-reference. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2, 353–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2003b). Being no one. The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. (1985). The ontogeny of information: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, D. I., Harries, M. H., Bevan, R., Thomas, S., Benson, P. J., Mistlin, A. J., et al. (1989). Frameworks of analysis for the neural representation of animate objects and actions. Journal of Experimental Biology, 146, 87–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, D. I., Mistlin, A. J., Harries, M. H., & Chitty, A. J. (1990). Understanding the visual appearance and consequence of hand actions. In M. A. Goodale (Ed.), Vision and action: The control of grasping (pp. 163–342). Norwood: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1962). Play, dreams, and imitation in childhood. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Trans. Gattegno & Hodgson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poeck, K. (1964). Phantoms following amputation in early childhood and in congenital absence of limbs. Cortex, 1, 269–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, E. H. (2006). A critical review of congenital phantom limb cases and a developmental theory for the basis of body image. Consciousness and Cognition, 15, 310–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, L. (2004). The mirror-neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (1996). Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research, 3, 131–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2001). Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understanding and imitation of action. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 661–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saadah, E. S. M., & Melzack, R. (1994). Phantom limb experiences in congenital limb-deficient adults. Cortex, 30, 479–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2003). Kinesthetic memory. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum, 7, 69–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simion, F., Regolin, L., & Bulf, H. (2008). A predisposition for biological motion in the newborn baby. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 105(2), 809–813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmel, M. L. (1966). Developmental aspects of the body scheme. Child Development, 37, 83–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stuart, S. A. J. (2006). “Extended body, extended mind: the self as prosthesis”, in screen consciousness: Mind, cinema and world. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2005). Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, 4(4), 407–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life. Biology: Phenomenology and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M., & Haggard, P. (2005). The rubber hand illusion revisited: visuotactile integration and self-attribution. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 31, 80–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Economo, C. (1929). The cytoarchitectonics of the human cerebral cortex. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallon, H. (1947) “Les origines de la pensee chez l’enfant”/“The Origins of Thought in the Child”. In The World of Henri Wallon, trans. Michael Vale. Jason Aronson (1984).

  • Wallon, H. (1965) “L’evolution psychologique de l’enfant”/“The Psychological Development of the Child”. In The World of Henri Wallon, trans. Michael Vale. Jason Aronson (1984).

  • Weinstein, S., & Sersen, E. A. (1961). Phantoms in cases of congenital absence of limbs. Neurology, 11, 905–911.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinstein, S., Sersen, E. A., & Vetter, R. J. (1964). Phantoms and somatic sensation in cases of congenital aplasia. Cortex, 1, 276–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005) Being someone. Psyche, 11/5, 1–20. Retrieved February 3, 2009, from http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/.

  • Zoia, S., Blason, L., D’Ottavio, G., Bulgheroni, M., Pezzetta, E., Scabar, A., et al. (2007). Evidence of early development of action planning in the human foetus: a kinematic study. Experimental Brain Research, 176, 217–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank Vittorio Gallese, Alessandra Umilta and Ezequiel Di Paolo for helpful discussions on the themes of this paper. RW’s work on this paper was supported by the EU Marie Curie - Research Training Network 035975 “DISCOS - Disorders and coherence of the embodied self”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Susan A. J. Stuart.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Wood, R., Stuart, S.A.J. Aplasic phantoms and the mirror neuron system: An enactive, developmental perspective. Phenom Cogn Sci 8, 487–504 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-009-9138-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-009-9138-2

Keywords

Navigation