Skip to main content
Log in

Assessing the influence of Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions

  • Essay Review
  • Published:
Metascience Aims and scope

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. Not all textbooks in philosophy of science include excerpts from Structure. Neither Marc Lange’s (2007) textbook, Philosophy of Science, nor Balashov and Rosenberg’s (2002) Philosophy of Science include excerpts from Structure, though both include a piece by Kuhn, “Objectivity, Value judgment, and Theory Choice.” There is another type of introductory textbook in philosophy of science, a single-authored textbook. These also give attention to Kuhn’s view. Peter Godfrey-Smith’s (2003) Theory and Reality contains two chapters devoted to Kuhn: “Kuhn and Normal Science” and “Kuhn and Revolutions.”.

  2. At least some of his early readers regarded the book as a challenge to positivism. In a review of Structure, Mary Hesse (1963) notes that “Kuhn has … outlined a new epistemological paradigm which promises to resolve some of the crises currently troubling empiricist philosophy of science” (287).

  3. There is, though, a growing body of scholarship in the history of philosophy of science addressing Kuhn, and the writing of Structure. See, for example, Hoyningen-Huene (2006) and Kindi (2005).

  4. A number of scholars have examined and continue to examine whether specific instances of theory change in a variety of fields are aptly characterized as Kuhnian revolutions. See, for example, Mayr (2004), Hoyningen-Huene (2008), and Marx and Bornmann (2010).

  5. To the title question of his paper “Did Tom Kuhn actually Meet Tom Bayes?” Lefteris Farmakis (2008) answers “no.”.

References

  • Andersen, H., P. Barker, and X. Chen. 2006. The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Balashov, Y., and A. Rosenberg eds. 2002. Philosophy of science: Contemporary readings. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, P. 2001. Kuhn, incommensurability, and cognitive science. Perspectives on Science 9(4): 433–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A.J. 2002. Kuhn’s wrong turn. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 33: 443–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. 2000. Thomas Kuhn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. 2005. Incommensurability reconsidered. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 36(1): 149–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H.I. 1983. Incommensurability. Inquiry 26(1): 3–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchwald, J.Z., and G.E. Smith. 1997. Thomas S. Kuhn, 1922–1996. Philosophy of Science 64(2): 361–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cedarbaum, D.G. 1983. Paradigms. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 14(3): 173–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curd, M., and J.A. Cover eds. 1998. Philosophy of science: The central issues. New York: W. W. Norton and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, F. 2005. Kuhn’s risk-spreading argument and the organization of scientific communities. Episteme 3: 201–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Oliveira, J.C.P. 2007. Carnap, Kuhn, and revisionism: On the publication of structure in encyclopedia. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 38: 147–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farmakis, L. 2008. Did Tom Kuhn actually meet Tom Bayes? Erkenntnis 68: 41–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1993. Remarks on the history of science and the history of philosophy. In World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science, ed. P. Horwich, 37–54. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. 2000. Thomas Kuhn: A philosophical history for our times. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2003. Theory and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. 1963. Review of The structure of scientific revolutions by Thomas S Kuhn. Isis 54(2): 286–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. 2008. Thomas Kuhn and the chemical revolution. Foundations of Chemistry 10: 101–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. 2006. More letters by Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on proto-structure. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 37: 610–632.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P., and H. Sankey eds. 2001. Incommensurability and related matters. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G., and T. Grünberg. 1995. Carnap and Kuhn: Arch-enemies of close allies? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46: 285–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kindi, V. 2005. The relation of history of science to philosophy of science in The structure of scientific revolutions and Kuhn’s later philosophical work. Perspectives on Science 13(4): 495–530.

  • Kourany, J.A. ed. 1998. Scientific knowledge: Basic issues in the philosophy of science, 2nd ed. Belmont CA: Wadsworth.

  • Kuhn, T. S. 2000. The road since structure: philosophical essays, 19701993, with an autobiographical interview, eds. J. Conant and J. Haugeland. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1987. Black-body theory and the quantum discontinuity, 1894–1912. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Lakatos, I., and A. Musgrave eds. 1970. Criticism and the growth of knowledge: Proceedings of the international colloquium in the philosophy of science, London, 1965, Vol. 4, reprinted with corrections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lange, M. ed. 2007. Philosophy of science: An anthology. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. 1984. Science and values: The aims of science and their role in scientific debate. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, W., and L. Bornmann. 2010. How accurately does Thomas Kuhn’s model of paradigm change describe the transition from the static view of the universe to the Big Bang theory in cosmology? Scientometrics 84(2): 441–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masterman, M. 1970. The nature of a paradigm, in Lakatos and Musgrave (1970), pp. 59–89.

  • Mayr, E. 2004. Do Thomas Kuhn’s scientific revolutions take place?. In What makes biology unique?: Considerations on the autonomy of a scientific discipline, 159–169. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • McGrew, T., M. Alspector-Kelly, and F. Allhoff. 2009. Philosophy of science: An historical anthology. Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Smith, W.H. ed. 2000. A companion to the philosophy of science. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Nickles, T. ed. 2003. Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oberheim, E. 2005. On the historical origins of the contemporary notion of incommensurability: Paul Feyerabend’s assault on conceptual conservativism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 36(2): 363–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, J. 2004. Bird, Kuhn, and positivism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35: 327–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S., and M. Curd. 2008. Routledge companion to philosophy of science. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G.A. 2005. How the cold war transformed philosophy of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G.A. 1991. Did Kuhn kill logical empiricism? Philosophy of Science 58(2): 264–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothbart, D. 1998. Science, reason, and reality: Issues in the philosophy of science. Forth Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace College Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A. 2007. The sort of everyday image of logical positivism: Thomas Kuhn and the decline of logical empiricist philosophy of science. In The Cambridge companion to logical empiricism, ed. A. Richardson, and T. Uebel, 346–369. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Sankey, H. 1993. Kuhn’s changing conception of incommensurability. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44(4): 759–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sankey, H. 1991. Incommensurability, translation, and understanding. Philosophical Quarterly 41(165): 414–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapere, D. 1964/1980. Review of The structure of scientific revolutions. In Paradigms and revolutions: Applications and appraisals of Thomas Kuhn’s philosophy of science, ed. G. Gutting. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Torres, J.M. 2010. On Kuhn’s philosophy and its legacy. Lisbon: Cadernos de Filosofia das Ciências.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K.B. 2011. Kuhn’s evolutionary social epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to K. Brad Wray.

Additional information

This essay review was especially commissioned on the occasion of the 50th anniversary of the publication of Kuhn’s seminal book. It continues the series of re-appraisals of older classics.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Wray, K.B. Assessing the influence of Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions . Metascience 21, 1–10 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-011-9603-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-011-9603-8

Navigation