Skip to navigation – Site map

HomeNuméros22Vindicating Avowal Expressivism: ...

Vindicating Avowal Expressivism: A Note on Rosenthal’s Performance-Conditional Equivalence Thesis

Nadja-Mira Yolcu
p. 188-198

Abstract

The paper comments on David Rosenthal’s claim that saying “p” is performance-conditionally equivalent to saying “I believe that p”. It is argued, by way of counterexamples, that the proposed performance-conditional equivalence does not hold in this generality. The paper further proposes that avowal expressivism gives necessary conditions for the performance-conditional equivalence: it holds only if the speaker’s utterance of “p” is a non-explicit expressive act expressive of the belief that p and the utterance of “I believe that p” is an explicit expressive act expressive of the very same belief. If that is correct, the performance-conditional equivalence thesis provides an argument against Rosenthal’s preferred avowal descriptivism and in favor of avowal expressivism.

Top of page

Editor’s notes

DOI: https://doi.org/ 10.17454/pam-2216

Full text

I thank the members of the research colloquium of the Chair for Theoretical Philosophy at the University of Mannheim and the participants of the 2021 San Raffaele School of Philosophy for valuable feedback. My special thanks go to Wolfgang Freitag, Dorit Bar-On, Mitchell Green, Maximilian Philipps, Helge Rückert and two anonymous reviewers of this journal for very helpful comments on previous drafts. I am grateful to Christopher von Bülow for proofreading and editing and to the Fritz Thyssen Stiftung for financially supporting this research.

  • 1Proponents of avowal descriptivism are, e.g., Rosenthal (1986, p. 75; 1993, pp. 49–50; 1995; 2010) (...)

1We regularly avow being in mental states. Avowals are serious and competent utterances of present-tense self-ascriptions of mental states, like “I believe that it’s raining”, “I am annoyed” or “I like you”. The most straightforward analysis of avowals is descriptivism. According to avowal descriptivism, avowals of the form “I ψ ((that p)/(o))”, with the dominant verb ψ referring to a psychological state, p for a proposition and o for an object, function as assertions about the speaker’s mental state of ψ-ing and are expressive of the belief that the speaker is ψ-ing. Descriptivists further deny that avowals are expressive of the speaker’s (first-order) ψ-ing. That is, on a descriptivist view, serious and competent utterances of “I believe that it’s raining”, “I am annoyed” and “I like you” function as reports about the speaker’s mental states.1

2There is a challenge to this position which motivates a different account of avowals. David Rosenthal – an avowal descriptivist – formulates it as follows:

[W]hen I say ‘I doubt it’ […] it seems natural to take me to be expressing my doubt, and not just reporting what mental state I am in. […] If you ask me whether it is raining and I say ‘I think so’, it would be bizarre to take me to be talking about my mental state, rather than the weather. (Rosenthal, 1993, p. 69)

  • 2For expressivist proposals, see, e.g., Wittgenstein (1953), Finkelstein (2003), Bar-On (2004), Fre (...)

3Considerations such as these (paired with the idea that avowals exhibit some kind of first-person authority) have led some to propose avowal expressivism: the thesis that serious and competent utterances of the form “I ψ ((that p)/(o))” are typically expressive of the (speaker’s) first-order mental state of ψ-ing. On expressivist views, with a serious and competent utterance of “I believe that it’s raining”, “I am annoyed” or “I like you” the speaker typically expresses a first-order belief about the weather, annoyance or affection for the addressee, respectively.2

  • 3Rosenthal uses “I think that p”. Since he seems to use thought in the sense of belief, I use “beli (...)

4Rosenthal admits (as do other descriptivists) that we often use “I believe that p3 instead of “p” – we use the two interchangeably. While the expressivist takes this to show that, in these cases, a speaker’s avowal “I believe that p” serves the same expressive function as her utterance of “p”, namely expressing the speaker’s belief that p, Rosenthal denies this thesis. He wants to uphold avowal descriptivism, yet concludes that utterances of “p” and “I believe that p” are performance-conditionally equivalent:

  • 4According to Rosenthal, the relevant qualification is that “the sentence ‘I think it’s raining’ ca (...)

Let’s assume the commonsense view that the speech act ‘I think it’s raining’ reports, but does not also express, one’s thought that it’s raining, and that the remark, ‘It’s raining’, does express that thought. […] Nevertheless, the two remarks have, with a qualification that does not matter for our purposes, the same conditions of use, that is, the same conditions for the appropriate performance of speech acts that use those sentences. The speech acts are, we can say, performance conditionally equivalent. (Rosenthal, 2010, p. 28)4

  • 5I assume that Rosenthal uses “saying” in the thick sense of the word, meaning “asserting” and not (...)

5He generalizes from this instance and claims that there is a performance-conditional equivalence “between saying that p and saying that one thinks that p” (Rosenthal, 2010, pp. 31-32). Thus, Rosenthal claims that assertions5 of sentences of the form

(1) “p”,

and

(2) “I believe that p

are performance-conditionally equivalent. He bases this generalization on utterances of

(3) “It’s raining”,

and

(4) “I believe that it’s raining”.

6While serious and competent utterances of (3) and (4) can be, and indeed often are, used interchangeably – they often serve the same function in a discourse – I will argue that assertions of forms (1) and (2) are not performance-conditionally equivalent. After briefly introducing Rosenthal’s performance-conditional equivalence thesis in Section 1, I present counterexamples to this generalization in Section 2. Based on Freitag’s theory of explicit expressives, Section 3 explains what goes wrong in the counterexamples and offers an expressivist explanation of the specific performance-conditional equivalence of utterances of (3) and (4). The discussion strongly suggests a necessary condition for the performance-conditional equivalence of utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2): the respective expressive acts need to have identical expressive content; that is, they need to be expressive of the same mental state. That avowal expressivism explains performance-conditional equivalence has also been noted by Dorit Bar-On (2010, pp. 54-55, 59). My expressivist account of performance-conditional equivalence is in the same spirit, and I aim to support this thesis by providing examples where the performance-conditional equivalence thesis and the assumption of avowal descriptivism lead one astray. I conclude that the performance-conditional equivalence thesis does not hold under a descriptivist analysis of avowals but rather requires avowal expressivism.

1. The Performance-Conditional Equivalence Thesis

7Let’s start with serious and competent utterances of (3) and (4). Usually, “I believe that it’s raining” functions to convey the same information as “It’s raining”: With both utterances the speaker conveys information about the weather – that it is raining – as well as about herself, namely that she believes that it’s raining. “I believe that it’s raining” and “It’s raining” can thus often be used interchangeably. We can similarly observe that “Ouch!” and “I am in pain” (or “It hurts”) can usually be used interchangeably, just as much as “Thank you!” and “I am grateful” (Rosenthal, 2010, p. 28; 1986, p. 74). Based on these observations, and with avowal descriptivism in the background, Rosenthal proposes the following principle of performance-conditional equivalence:

  • 6This is a slightly modified version of how Rosenthal puts it in 1995, p. 322. Compare Searle (1979 (...)

(P) (Typically,) speech acts and assertions of self-ascriptions of those mental states of which the respective speech act is expressive are (roughly) performance-conditionally equivalent.6

8The performance-conditional equivalence described in (P) is qualified in two ways. First, there is a restriction to typical contexts. For instance, sometimes one might say “I believe that p” without being willing or able to say “p”. Consider the following case of psychotherapy: After several sessions, her psychotherapist has finally convinced Sally that she believes that her brother is angry with her (e.g., as a result of some quarrel back in their childhood). Sally now believes that she believes that her brother is angry with her. Thus, Sally would aptly report on her mental state by asserting “I believe that my brother is angry with me”, thereby expressing her higher-order belief that she believes that her brother is angry with her. She would, however, not assert “My brother is angry with me”, for the therapist has also convinced her that, although she has this deep-rooted belief, that belief is mistaken and her brother is in fact not (or no longer) angry with her (for a similar example, compare also Bar-On, 2010, p. 54). Rosenthal cannot explain this mismatch but just dismisses it by claiming that these contexts are quite rare and restricts performance-conditional equivalence to typical contexts (2010, p. 29).

  • 7For an overview of mitigation, compare Thaler (2012). For an overview of hedged assertion, compare (...)

9Second, according to (P), if the two acts are performance-conditionally equivalent, they are not fully but only roughly equivalent. This restriction is supposed to account for the phenomenon of hedging. For instance, if “I believe that p” is used to assert that p, which it can be but need not be, the assertion that p has only weakened assertive force – it is a hedged assertion.7

  • 8Let’s pause here. While (P) seems plausible for the pairs “Thank you!” and “I am grateful (to you) (...)

10It’s not entirely clear how Rosenthal explains the performance-conditional equivalence specified in (P). Using a factive, causal notion of expression (1986, p. 78; 1993, p. 56; 1995, pp. 316, 324; 2010, p. 25), Rosenthal holds that sincere speech acts express those mental states by which they are (partly) caused. A speaker’s sincere “Thank you!” expresses gratitude, a speaker’s sincere promise “I’ll be there” expresses an intention to show up and a speaker’s sincere “Ouch!” expresses pain. In light of this correspondence between (sincere) illocutionary acts and expressions of mental states, Rosenthal assigns the corresponding self-ascriptions of mental states the same use conditions (Rosenthal, 2010, p. 32): Whenever one says “Thank you!”, one is “roughly equally disposed to say” (p. 29) “I am grateful”, and whenever one promises to be there, one might just as well have said “I intend to be there”.8 Nevertheless, according to Rosenthal, serious and competent utterances of self-ascriptions of mental states have assertive force and thus express the speaker’s belief that she herself is in the mental state named. So, while, for instance, “I am grateful” can be used instead of “Thank you!”, the former does not function as an expression of gratitude but is expressive of the speaker’s belief that she herself is grateful.

11With (P) and avowal descriptivism in the background, Rosenthal concludes that assertions of forms (1) and (2) are generally performance-conditionally equivalent:

[T]he speech acts of asserting that p and asserting that I think that p, though they differ in respect to their truth conditions, have roughly the same conditions of assertibility. Any circumstances in which I could say that p are circumstances in which I could say I think that p. (Rosenthal, 1995, p. 320)

12This generalization is incorrect. In the next section, I provide examples of utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2) for which (P) together with the assumption of avowal descriptivism predicts performance-conditional equivalence even though, in the most plausible contexts, the respective pairs are not performance-conditionally equivalent. (P) together with the assumption of avowal descriptivism predicts performance-conditional equivalence where there is none.

2. Against the General Performance-Conditional Equivalence of (1) and (2)

13Far from denying the connection between certain illocutionary acts and the expression of corresponding mental states, I think it is precisely because of this connection that Rosenthal’s general thesis of the performance-conditional equivalence of assertions of sentences of forms (1) and (2) is incorrect. Utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2) are performance-conditionally equivalent only if the utterance of an indicative sentence of form “p” is indeed used as an assertion, or at least as an expression of the belief that p, and the utterance of (2) serves to express that very same belief. Only if that’s the case, as it usually is for the pair of (3) and (4), can sentences of forms (1) and (2) be used interchangeably. However, it is not the case that all serious and competent utterances of an indicative sentence “p” are assertions, or even expressions of a belief that p. This is especially vivid in those cases where “p” is a present-tense mental state self-ascription. Consider the following pairs:

(5)    “I like you.”

(6)    “I believe I like you.”

(7)    “I am afraid.”

(8)    “I believe I am afraid.”

(9)    “I hope that it’s raining.”

(10)    “I believe I hope that it’s raining.”

  • 9Consider also the following example inspired by a remark of Wittgenstein’s. Wittgenstein notes tha (...)

14All three pairs have the syntactical form of pair (1) and (2). Thus, if Rosenthal’s avowal descriptivism is correct and if (P) holds for assertions of sentences of forms (1) and (2), then (P) also holds for the above pairs. That is, it should be possible to use the members of each pair of sentences interchangeably; their utterances should be performance-conditionally equivalent. But utterances of the members of these pairs are not performance-conditionally equivalent – at least not typically.9

15Consider this for (5) and (6). A newly won friend wants to hear me say (5) “I like you” and is rather disappointed if I just tell her (6) “I believe I like you”. What she wants to be assured of is that I like her and not merely that I believe I like her. After all, I might be mistaken in my belief and not like her at all. Sensitive to this possibility, she will only take assurance of my affection for her from an utterance of (5) but not of (6) – even if (6) does not convey any hesitance on my part. And if I repeatedly use (6) instead of (5), showing no regard for the difference, she might become exceedingly cross with me (compare Williams, 2013, p. 1126, for similar examples). (Similar considerations hold for the other pairs.)

16If serious and competent utterances of (5) and (6) are not performance-conditionally equivalent and the pair has the form of pair (1) and (2), then assertions of sentences of forms (1) and (2) are not performance-conditionally equivalent – or utterances of self-ascriptions of mental states are not (always) assertions (without any first-order expressive content) after all. Thus, given the lack of performance-conditional equivalence for utterances of (5) and (6), (P) needs to be restricted or avowal descriptivism must be given up.

  • 10One way to go might be to insist that sameness or difference in performance-conditions (also) rest (...)

17Some might attempt to save avowal descriptivism by reference to hedging. They might argue that with (6) the speaker is weakly asserting that she likes the addressee. There are two ways to go from here: Either one insists that utterances of (5) and (6) are performance-conditionally equivalent after all – with (6) one just asserts shyly that one likes the addressee. Or one agrees that utterances of (5) and (6) are usually not performance-conditionally equivalent but attributes this to the latter functioning as a hedged assertion that the speaker likes the addressee. (Corresponding considerations hold for (7) and (8), and (9) and (10).) Let’s assume that the avowal descriptivist grants that utterances of (5) and (6) are typically not performance-conditionally equivalent. While there is indeed some weakening of illocutionary force if (6) is used as an assertion that one likes the addressee, the same holds for assertions of (2) and (4). Anyone taking this route while agreeing that utterances of (5) and (6) are typically not performance-conditionally equivalent and upholding (a restricted version of) (P), would need to explain why hedging or hesitation precludes performance-conditional equivalence for utterances of (5) and (6) but not of (3) and (4).10

18In light of counterexamples (5)–(10), I propose to give up avowal descriptivism, which also leads to a modification of (P). In the next section, I offer an expressivist explanation for why utterances of (5) and (6) are usually not performance-conditionally equivalent while utterances of (3) and (4) are. The problem with utterances of (5) and (6) is not that the speaker makes assertions with the same content, albeit of different assertive strengths (here I echo Rosenthal, 2010, p. 28, who claims that “degrees of confidence won’t be relevant”). Instead, utterances of (5) and (6), irrespective of the strength of their respective illocutionary force, if they function as illocutionary acts at all, usually have different expressive contents. That’s why they are typically not performance-conditionally equivalent.

3. An Expressivist Explanation of Performance-Conditional Equivalence

19The counterexamples strongly suggest that avowal descriptivism and, thus, also (P), as specified above, are incorrect. While there is, under certain circumstances, a performance-conditional equivalence between speech acts and serious and competent utterances of present-tense self-ascriptions of those mental states of which the respective speech acts are expressive, the lack of performance-conditional equivalence in pairs (5)–(10) points to the fact that, often, serious and competent utterances of self-ascriptions of mental states are simply not assertions about one’s mental states (or they are, at least, also expressive of the mental state named). Avowal descriptivism is incorrect and (P) needs to be modified.

  • 11In many respects, Freitag’s theory of explicit expressive acts shares the spirit of Bar-On’s neo-e (...)

20I propose to go expressivist. The central expressivist thesis with respect to avowals – going back at least to Wittgenstein – is that in uttering a present-tense self-ascription of a mental state, the speaker typically expresses the first-order mental state named (see, e.g., Bar-On, 2004, p. 330). As Wittgenstein holds, in affirming “I hope he’ll come” (1953, PI §585), a speaker expresses hope, with “I am in pain” (1953, PI §244) she expresses pain, and with “I am afraid” (1953, PI II ix) she expresses fear. I will now give a very rough sketch of Wolfgang Freitag’s theory of expressives, which I follow in this paper (for a more comprehensive introduction, see Freitag, 2018; Freitag and Yolcu, 2021; and Freitag and Kraus, 2022).11

  • 12Some, however, hold that expression is factive and maintain that with an insincere illocutionary a (...)

21Given classical speech act theory (Austin, 1962; Searle, 1969), linguistic acts generally have an illocutionary and an expressive dimension. A serious and competent utterance of “It is raining”, for instance, provides twofold information. The speaker describes the world – she asserts that it is raining. But she also gives information about herself – she expresses a belief that it is raining. A serious and competent utterance of “It is raining” thus also functions as a non-explicit expressive act (Freitag, 2018, p. 59). So far, that’s standard and fairly uncontroversial.12 The theory of expressives takes this part of expressivism as given.

22The central expressivist thesis is that there are also explicit expressive acts (Freitag, 2018, p. 59): utterances in which the mental state expressed is made explicit in the utterance. Let’s consider this for doxastic avowals. A serious and competent utterance of “I believe that it is raining” typically gives the same two-fold information as “It is raining”. With “I believe that it is raining” the speaker typically expresses a belief that it is raining as a direct, explicit expressive act and she might assert that it is raining as an indirect illocutionary act. With both utterances – “It is raining” and “I believe that it is raining” – the speaker expresses a belief that it is raining; by uttering “It is raining” she does so non-explicitly and by uttering “I believe that it is raining” she does so explicitly.

  • 13Compare Searle (1983, p. 6).
  • 14Since, on my view, expression is non-factive, the speaker might not be in the mental state express (...)

23Expressive acts have expressive contents: in performing an expressive act, the speaker expresses a mental state. Expressive contents C are made up of a psychological mode13 and a mental state content (at least for intentional mental states). For instance, with β for belief, p for that it is raining and S indicating the speaker, the non-explicit expressive act performed in seriously and competently uttering “It is raining” and the explicit expressive act performed with “I believe that it is raining” have the same expressive content, namely βS(p).14 Similarly, with γ representing gratitude, the non-explicit expressive act performed with “Thank you!” and the explicit expressive act performed with “I am grateful to you” both have γS(you) as their expressive contents. And, with π representing pain, the non-explicit expressive “Ouch!” and the explicit expressive “I am in pain” have identical expressive contents, namely πS.

  • 15Note that avowal expressivism, as presented here, is not a semantic thesis. The semantic content o (...)

24Of course, Freitag’s theory of expressives does not deny that self-ascriptions of mental states can be used to report on one’s own mental states. Self-ascriptions of mental states of the form “I ψ ((that p)/(o))” have two uses: depending on context, they can be used as explicit expressive acts or as non-explicit expressive acts (Freitag, 2018, p. 66; compare Bar-On, 2004, p. 303). In the latter case, the relevant avowal is indeed expressive of the belief that the speaker is ψ-ing and functions as an assertion that she is ψ-ing.15

25Armed with the theory of (explicit) expressive acts, let’s return to the (alleged) performance-conditional equivalence of serious and competent utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2). What goes wrong for utterances of (5) and (6)? Typically, utterances of (5) and (6) cannot (adequately) be used interchangeably, for they have different expressive contents. With a serious and competent utterance of (5) “I like you” the speaker usually does not assert that she likes the addressee. Nor does she express a belief that she likes the addressee. Instead, “I like you” serves to express the speaker’s liking the addressee. An utterance of (6) “I believe I like you”, however, does not serve to express the speaker’s liking the addressee. Instead, in its explicit-expressive use it is expressive of the speaker’s belief that she likes the addressee, and in its non-explicit-expressive use it is expressive of the speaker’s second-order belief that she herself believes that she likes the addressee. That’s why serious and competent utterances of (5) and (6) are typically not performance-conditionally equivalent: they usually function as expressive acts with different expressive contents.

26Avowal expressivism does not only explain why utterances of (5) and (6) are usually not performance-conditionally equivalent. It can also account for cases where (5) and (6) can indeed be used interchangeably (these are admittedly very special contexts). Utterances of (5) and (6) are performance-conditionally equivalent only if (5) is used as a non-explicit expressive act expressive of the speaker’s belief that she likes the addressee and (6) is used as an explicit expressive act expressive of the very same belief. Only then do utterances of (5) and (6) serve to express the same expressive content. (A similar reasoning applies to (7) and (8), and (9) and (10).)

27This analysis carries over to utterances of (3) and (4). They are performance-conditionally equivalent only if (3) is used as a non-explicit expressive act expressive of the belief that it is raining and (4) is used as an explicit expressive act expressive of the belief that it is raining as well. If (4), however, is used as a non-explicit expressive act expressive of the speaker’s belief that she herself believes that it is raining, the expressive contents of utterances (3) and (4) diverge and the two utterances are not performance-conditionally equivalent.

  • 16Here, I focus on the expressive dimension of speech. Performance-conditional equivalence might als (...)

28The expressivist proposal, thus, has more explanatory power than (P) and avowal descriptivism. It can explain when utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2) are performance-conditionally equivalent and when they are not, as it is usually the case for utterances of (5) and (6). The discussion strongly suggests that utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2) are performance-conditionally equivalent only if the utterance of a sentence of form (1) is an expression of the belief that p and the utterance of a sentence of form (2) functions to express that very same belief. That is, utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2) are performance-conditionally equivalent only if (1) is used as a non-explicit expressive act, expressing the speaker’s belief that p, and (2) is used as an explicit expressive act, also expressing the speaker’s belief that p. Only if an utterance of (2) makes explicit what is implicit in an utterance of (1), namely that the speaker believes that p, can (1) and (2) be used interchangeably – their utterances then function to convey the same information: that the speaker believes that p.16

29But if an utterance of a sentence of form (1) does not serve to express the speaker’s belief that p but a different mental state, as is usually the case for utterances of (5), (7) and (9), and that mental state differs from the one expressed when uttering a sentence of form (2), then the two utterances are not performance-conditionally equivalent. Accordingly, I propose to revise (P):

(P*) Speech acts and serious and competent utterances of self-ascriptions of those mental states of which the respective speech act is expressive are (roughly) performance-conditionally equivalent only if their expressive contents are identical.

  • 17(P*) generalizes beyond the doxastic case. With the same structure, we can give a necessary condit (...)

30Performance-conditional equivalence of speech acts of forms (1) and (2) requires identical expressive content. The expressive contents of serious and competent utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2) are identical if and only if the former is a non-explicit and the latter an explicit expressive act. Hence, performance-conditional equivalence of speech acts of forms (1) and (2) requires avowal expressivism.17

4. Conclusion

  • 18If the mark of performance-conditional equivalence is identical expressive content, we might not n (...)

31I have presented counterexamples against the general performance-conditional equivalence of assertions of forms (1) and (2). In response, I have offered an expressivist way of distinguishing between utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2) which are performance-conditionally equivalent and such which are not. Only if the expressive content of the expressive act performed with an utterance of a sentence of form (1) matches that of the expressive act performed with an utterance of a sentence of form (2) are the two utterances performance-conditionally equivalent.18 The phenomenon that utterances of (3) and (4) can often be used interchangeably, which Rosenthal correctly identifies, can thus be explained by reference to a theory of expressive acts: With a serious and competent utterance of (3) the speaker non-explicitly expresses the belief that it’s raining. And an utterance of (4) usually serves to express that very same belief explicitly. Only if we have this match of implicit and explicit expression of the very same belief are utterances of (3) and (4) performance-conditionally equivalent. Thus, avowal expressivism does not only explain the frequent interchangeability of speech acts of forms (1) and (2) and gives a necessary condition for their performance-conditional equivalence, but the thesis of performance-conditional equivalence even provides an argument in favor of avowals having first-order expressive content.

Top of page

Bibliography

Austin, J.L. (1962). How to Do Things with Words (2nd ed.). Edited by J.O. Urmson & M. Sbisà. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.

Bar-On, D. (2004). Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Bar-On, D. (2010). Avowals: Expression, Security, and Knowledge: Reply to Matthew Boyle, David Rosenthal, and Maura Tumulty. Acta Analytica, 25: 47-63.

Benton, M.A., van Elswyk, P. (2020). Hedged Assertion. In S. Goldberg (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Assertion. New York: Oxford University Press, 245-263.

Davis, W.A. (2003). Meaning, Expressing and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Eriksson, J. (2010). Self-expression, Expressiveness, and Sincerity. Acta Analytica, 25: 71-79.

Finkelstein, D.H. (2003). Expression and the inner. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.

Freitag, W. (2018). Wittgenstein on ‘I believe’. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(1): 54-69.

Freitag, W., Yolcu, N.M. (2021). An Expressivist Solution to Moorean Paradoxes. Synthese, 199: 5001-5024.

Freitag, W., Kraus, K.T. (2022). An Expressivist Interpretation of Kant’s ‘I think’. Noûs, 56(1): 110-132.

Green, M.S. (2007). How Do Speech Acts Express Psychological States? In S.L. Tsohatzidis (ed.), John Searle’s Philosophy of Language: Force, Meaning and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 267-284.

Green, M.S. (2009). Speech Acts, the Handicap Principle and the Expression of Psychological States. Mind & Language, 24(2): 139-163.

Kaplan, D. (1999). The Meaning of ‘Ouch’ and ‘Oops’: Explorations in the Theory of Meaning as Use. 2004 version, University of California, Los Angeles (unpublished manuscript).

Owens, D. (2006). Testimony and Assertion. Philosophical Studies, 130: 105-129.

Rosenthal, D.M. (1986). Intentionality. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10: 151-184. Reprinted in D.M. Rosenthal, Consciousness and Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005, 71-99.

Rosenthal, D.M. (1993). Thinking That One Thinks. In M. Davies & G.W. Humphreys (eds.), Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 197-223. Reprinted in D.M. Rosenthal, Consciousness and Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005, 46-70.

Rosenthal, D.M. (1995). Moore’s Paradox and Consciousness. Philosophical Perspectives, 9: 313-333.

Rosenthal, D.M. (2010). Expressing One’s Mind. Acta Analytica, 25: 21-34.

Searle, J.R. (1969). Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Searle, J.R. (1979). Expression and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Searle, J.R. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Siebel, M. (2020). The Belief View of Assertion. In S.C. Goldberg (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Assertion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 99-118.

Thaler, V. (2012). Mitigation as Modification of Illocutionary Force. Journal of Pragmatics, 44: 907-919.

Williams, J.N. (2013). Moore’s Paradox and the Priority of Belief Thesis. Philosophical Studies, 165: 1117-1138.

Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology (vol. I). Edited by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.

Top of page

Notes

1Proponents of avowal descriptivism are, e.g., Rosenthal (1986, p. 75; 1993, pp. 49–50; 1995; 2010), Kaplan (1999) and Green (2009).

2For expressivist proposals, see, e.g., Wittgenstein (1953), Finkelstein (2003), Bar-On (2004), Freitag (2018), Freitag and Yolcu (2021), Freitag and Kraus (2022). Some expressivists propose that an avowal typically both functions as an assertion that one is in the mental state named and is expressive of that very (first-order) mental state (and expressive of the belief that one is in that (first-order) mental state due to the avowal’s functioning as an assertion) (see, e.g., Finkelstein, 2003, pp. 95–97). Avowal expressivism, as specified here, is compatible with the claim that avowals have assertive force. While the arguments given below go against avowal descriptivism, they might not exclude such a dual-act analysis of avowals. If that were the case, (P*) would need to be revised accordingly. Here, I will only be concerned with “pure” avowal expressivism.

3Rosenthal uses “I think that p”. Since he seems to use thought in the sense of belief, I use “believe” here (compare also Williams (2013) for this reading of Rosenthal).

4According to Rosenthal, the relevant qualification is that “the sentence ‘I think it’s raining’ can be used, in contrast to the sentence ‘It’s raining’, to indicate the speaker’s hesitation” (Rosenthal, 2010, p. 28). Rosenthal also notes that there are contexts where utterances of sentences of form “I think that p” “can also indicate dispositive certainty” and claims that “degrees of confidence won’t be relevant here” (p. 28).

5I assume that Rosenthal uses “saying” in the thick sense of the word, meaning “asserting” and not just “uttering” (compare also Rosenthal, 1995, p. 323).

6This is a slightly modified version of how Rosenthal puts it in 1995, p. 322. Compare Searle (1979, p. 54) and Freitag (2018) for similar principles.

7For an overview of mitigation, compare Thaler (2012). For an overview of hedged assertion, compare Benton & van Elswyk (2020).

8Let’s pause here. While (P) seems plausible for the pairs “Thank you!” and “I am grateful (to you)”, and “Ouch!” and “I am in pain”, it might be less plausible for “I’ll be there” and “I intend to be there”. After all, a serious and competent utterance of “I intend to be there” need not have commissive force. While it usually is a Moorean absurdity to affirm “I’ll be there but I don’t intend to be there”, it is perfectly fine to affirm “I intend to be there but I don’t promise to be there”. In seriously and competently uttering a self-ascription of intention, a speaker may make a promise but need not do so (and if she does, it’s probably weakened). The illocutionary act of promising to do something is more than merely expressing an intention to do something. That might be a difference between promising and thanking. (P), thus, seems doubtful for promises and avowals of the corresponding intention. Similar considerations hold for pairs of utterances of forms (1) and (2). Whether the qualification of “rough” equivalence can meet these worries, needs to be discussed.

9Consider also the following example inspired by a remark of Wittgenstein’s. Wittgenstein notes that “[t]he sentence ‘I want some wine to drink’ has roughly the same sense as ‘Wine over here!’ ” (Wittgenstein, 1980, RPP I §469). At least on the utterance level, any proponent of (P) needs to agree: The request “Wine over here!” and the utterance of a self-ascription of the corresponding desire “I want some wine to drink” typically have roughly the same use conditions. And if avowal descriptivism is correct and (P) holds for assertions of sentences of forms (1) and (2), then serious and competent utterances of “I want some wine to drink” and “I believe I want some wine to drink” can typically be used interchangeably. If that’s the case and we assume transitivity for (rough) performance-conditional equivalence, then the request “Wine over here!” and the serious and competent utterance of “I believe I want some wine to drink” have the same use conditions too. But that is surely not the case. A serious and competent utterance of “I believe I want some wine to drink” is not expressive of the speaker’s desire for wine, nor does it function as a request for wine. If I am sitting in the living room with some friends and tell them that I believe I want some wine to drink, they would surely not understand this as a request to bring me some wine. In this case, (P) and avowal descriptivism lead one astray.

10One way to go might be to insist that sameness or difference in performance-conditions (also) rests on other factors than the information conveyed (e.g., what is at stake in a context, or certain commitments the speaker undertakes in making an utterance). I appreciate that this may very well be. Nevertheless, I offer an elegant expressivist way to distinguish between cases in which serious and competent utterances of sentences of forms (1) and (2) are performance-conditionally equivalent and cases in which they are not. If other factors are relevant, or a different (descriptivist) explanation is supposedly more suitable, it is up to the avowal descriptivist to argue for it.

11In many respects, Freitag’s theory of explicit expressive acts shares the spirit of Bar-On’s neo-expressivism. For instance, both propose a distinction between sentence expression (s-expression in Bar-On’s terminology) and speaker expression (a-expression in Bar-On’s terminology) and maintain that present-tense self-ascriptions of mental states have a dual use. Nevertheless, there are differences. For instance, Freitag’s theory operates with a non-causal, non-factive notion of expression and puts emphasis on the connection between the illocutionary and the expressive dimensions of speech.

12Some, however, hold that expression is factive and maintain that with an insincere illocutionary act the speaker only purports to express the corresponding mental state (see, e.g., Rosenthal, 1986, pp. 87-93; 2010, p. 25; Owens, 2006, p. 113; compare Green, 2007). I will not debate the relation of illocution and expression in this paper (for a recent overview of the relation of assertion and belief expression, see Siebel, 2020). Here I assume that classical speech act theory is correct: When performing an illocutionary act which has a sincerity condition, the speaker is also performing an expressive act, irrespective of whether or not she actually is in the corresponding mental state. A speaker who performs an illocutionary act with a sincerity condition presents herself as being in that mental state which is specified in the sincerity condition. I assume a non-factive notion of expression: One can express a mental state even if one is not in that mental state (compare Searle, 1969, p. 65; Davis, 2003; Eriksson, 2010). I shall say that an expressive act is expressively correct (Kaplan, 1999) if and only if the speaker is indeed in the mental state expressed. My general argument, however, does not depend on the non-factivity of expression.

13Compare Searle (1983, p. 6).

14Since, on my view, expression is non-factive, the speaker might not be in the mental state expressed. Nevertheless, the mental state expressed is not someone else’s or just free-floating, rather it is the speaker herself who is supposedly in that mental state (as indicated by the subscript S).

15Note that avowal expressivism, as presented here, is not a semantic thesis. The semantic content of the sentence “I believe that it is raining” is that the speaker believes that it is raining, and the sentence is true if and only if she does so (see Freitag and Yolcu, 2021, p. 5019).

16Here, I focus on the expressive dimension of speech. Performance-conditional equivalence might also require an equivalence in the illocutionary dimension. Sentences of forms (1) and (2) can both be used to assert that p. While (2) need not be uttered with illocutionary force at all, an utterance of (2) can function, via conversational implicature (Freitag, 2018), as a hedged assertion that p.

17(P*) generalizes beyond the doxastic case. With the same structure, we can give a necessary condition for when, for instance, the speech act “Thank you!” and a serious and competent utterance of “I am grateful to you” are performance-conditionally equivalent. They are performance-conditionally equivalent only if the utterance of “Thank you!” functions as a non-explicit expressive act expressive of the speaker’s gratitude towards the addressee and the utterance of “I am grateful to you” functions as an explicit expressive act also expressive of the speaker’s gratitude towards the same addressee.

18If the mark of performance-conditional equivalence is identical expressive content, we might not need to restrict performance-conditional equivalence to speech acts, as done in (P*). If non-verbal expressive acts have performance-conditions, it might be possible to extend the equivalence to non-verbal expressive acts (compare Bar-On, 2010, p. 59).

Top of page

References

Bibliographical reference

Nadja-Mira Yolcu, “Vindicating Avowal Expressivism: A Note on Rosenthal’s Performance-Conditional Equivalence Thesis”Phenomenology and Mind, 22 | 2022, 188-198.

Electronic reference

Nadja-Mira Yolcu, “Vindicating Avowal Expressivism: A Note on Rosenthal’s Performance-Conditional Equivalence Thesis”Phenomenology and Mind [Online], 22 | 2022, Online since 01 August 2022, connection on 18 April 2024. URL: http://journals.openedition.org/phenomenology/1107

Top of page

About the author

Nadja-Mira Yolcu

University of Mannheim – nadja-mira.yolcu@uni-mannheim.de

Top of page

Copyright

CC-BY-4.0

The text only may be used under licence CC BY 4.0. All other elements (illustrations, imported files) are “All rights reserved”, unless otherwise stated.

Top of page
Search OpenEdition Search

You will be redirected to OpenEdition Search