Skip to main content
Log in

Hearing objects and events

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Through hearing we learn about source events: events in which objects move or interact so that they vibrate and produce sound waves, such as when they roll, collide, or scrape together. It is often claimed that we do not simply hear sounds and infer what event caused them, but hear source events themselves, through hearing sounds. Here I investigate how the idea that we hear source events should be understood, with a focus on how hearing an event relates to hearing the objects involved in that event. I argue that whereas we see events such as rollings and collisions by seeing objects move through space, this cannot be how we hear them, and go on to examine two other possible models. On the first, we hear events but not their participant objects. On the second, to hear an event is to hear the appearance of an object to change. I argue that neither is satisfactory and endorse a third option: to hear a source event is to hear an object as extending through time.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sound waves can of course also be produced by the movement of liquids or gases. Although I will talk only about material objects here, everything I say applies mutatis mutandis in these cases as well.

  2. In contemporary philosophy of perception, Matthen comes closest to a sounds only view of audition: “objects are characterizable by the sound they make—there are squeaky violins, baritone singers, alto saxophones—but the inferential path from auditory experience to such dispositional characterizations is quite indirect” (2005, p. 285). Martin says: “One may pick out the source of the sound via picking out the sound itself—we might then understand the demonstrative expression, ‘that dog’ as involving deferred ostension, perhaps as the descriptive phrase, ‘the dog which is actually the source of this sound’” (1997, p. 93) but has a less hardline view in his later work, saying that, in some cases at least, source events can be heard (2012, p. 348).

  3. This is in contrast to the sense-data theories of perception popular in the first half of the twentieth Century.

  4. Representationalists such as Cohen, Nanay, and Matthen hold that perceivers represent material objects and attribute, or predicate, properties to them, but relationalists also think that material objects are, fundamentally, what we see, in that perception consists in their standing in a certain type of relation to a subject. See, for example, Brewer (2007).

  5. Less mainstream views of vision can be found in Clark (2000) who argues that we see, first and foremost, places, portions of space, not the things which occupy them. And Matthen (2010) who suggests that we see two types of individual simultaneously: material objects, and the ambient light illuminating those objects.

  6. Property variation will be returned to later when change perception is discussed.

  7. We will see later that there is more to seeing movement than this.

  8. The degree to which audition provides spatial information is controversial See, for example, Strawson (1959, pp. 65–66) Casati and Dokic (2009).

  9. At least, no non-pathological equivalent. Patients suffering from simultanagnosia (a symptom of Bálint's syndrome) can perceive only one object at a time and are unable to locate that object in relation to others. It is possible that if a sufferer of simultanagnosia were able to track an object as it moves (those with this condition also have difficulty fixating on moving objects) they would perceive an object moving, but not see where it was moving from or to (see Rafal 1997, 2003). Thanks to an anonymous referee for drawing my attention to these cases.

  10. He also cites Strawson (1959), Dretske (1969, p. 20), Martin (2007, p. 706).

  11. I am also uncertain how such a claim can be reconciled with O’Callaghan’s stronger claims quoted at the beginning of this section.

  12. In more recent work, Kulvicki argues that “aspects of the events that cause vibrations, such as intensity, and properties of the spaces in which one hears” (2016, p. 91) are heard as well as stable vibratory properties. He does not, however, return to the question of how source hearing should be understood.

  13. This dual property account of colour constancy is somewhat similar to accounts proposed by Schellenberg (2008) and Shoemaker (2006).

  14. This idea has a long history and many variations. It can be traced back to William James’ notion of the specious present: “The practically cognized present is no knife-edge, but a saddle-back, with a certain breadth of its own on which we sit perched” (1890, Vol. I, p. 609).

  15. Although James suggested that the specious present could be as long as a minute, most contemporary versions of this idea estimate it to be much shorter. For example, Dainton (2000, p. 171) estimates it to be about half a second or less, Lockwood “a second or a second and a half’ (2005, p. 381), and Phillips supposes it to be approximately 300 ms (2011, p. 817).

  16. Using the temporal field as a means of differentiating perceptible and imperceptible change is based on Hoerl (2013, p. 18) and Phillips (2011, p. 11).

  17. Certain types of video playback can be thought of as something like the inverse of imperceptible change outlined at the beginning of this section: rapidly changing—rather than slow moving– stimuli can give rise to visual percepts of unchanging objects. The images on old cathode ray tube televisions, for example, are generated by electron beams illuminating different coloured pixels on the screen in rapid succession. Although most of the time this process will generate images of things moving or changing—people talking, balls rolling etc.—it is easy to think of cases in which the successive illumination of pixels generates images of entirely unchanging objects—people staring into the distance, balls at rest. Images generated in this way, however, still decompose in something like the same way as video files or frames of a film: any one of the pixels which make up an image could be presented to the viewer for a much longer time, giving rise to the perception of a single, unchanging, dot on the screen. I am grateful for an anonymous referee for drawing my attention to this type of case.

  18. This type of challenge was first put to me by Casey O’Callaghan.

  19. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing me on this point.

  20. Although Endurantism and Perdurantism can be thought of as the two main options for characterising persistence, there are various other possibilities, such as stage theory (Hawley 2001; Sider 2001).

  21. Prosser’s overall aim in this paper is to give an account of the phenomenology of temporal passage, the experience of time as flowing, which can be reconciled with metaphysical accounts on which time does not flow: “…a key factor in time seeming to pass is that change is experienced as dynamic, and change is experienced as dynamic because the experience involves the representation of something enduring through the change. It is this notion of a single entity passing ‘through’ a change that captures at least a very important element of the experience of temporal passage” (2012, p. 16). One cost of rejecting the idea that perceptual experience always presents objects as enduring is that it would appear Prosser’s account of experienced passage must be given up as well. Given that there are other accounts available as to why passage is experienced which do not rely on objects being experienced as enduring (e.g. Paul 2010; Skow 2015; Torrengo 2017), as well as doubts that there even is a phenomenology of passage (Hoerl 2014), I think that this is a price worth paying.

  22. Parsons (2000, 2004) proposes an alternative to the standard four dimensionalist model. He argues that one can accept objects are extended in time, without committing to the idea that they have temporal parts. Key to this is the idea that as well as possessing “qualities”, such as being red or being warm, objects can also possess spatial or temporal distributional properties, such as being polka-dotted, or being warm at one time and cold at another. On this account, objects endure, and yet are temporally extended. It is possible that the ideas I put forward in this section could be worked out in terms of temporally distributional properties, rather than temporal shape, although I do not see that very much hangs on this difference. Parsons suggests that shape is a “degenerate case” of a distributional property (2004, p. 4).

References

  • Berkeley, G. (2012). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. Peterborough: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2007). Perception and its objects. Philosophical Studies, 132(1), 87–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A., & Hilbert, D. (1997). Colors and reflectances. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26(1), 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casati, R., & Dokic, J. (2009). Some varieties of spatial hearing. In M. Nudds & C. O’Callaghan (Eds.), Sounds and perception: New philosophical essays (pp. 97–110). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2000). A theory of sentience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (2004). Objects, places, and perception. Philosophical Psychology, 17(4), 471–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. (2000). Stream of consciousness: Unity and continuity in conscious experience. Routledge: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. (2008). The experience of time and change. Philosophy Compass, 3(4), 619–638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. (2016). Time and space (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. I. (1969). Seeing and knowing. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2001). How things persist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, C. (2013). A succession of feelings, in and of itself, is not a feeling of succession. Mind, 122(486), 373–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, C. (2014). Do we (seem to) perceive passage? Philosophical Explorations, 17(2), 188–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology (Vol. 2). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1929/1781–7) Critique of pure reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan.

  • Kulvicki, J. (2008). The nature of noise. Philosophers’ Imprint, 8(11), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. (2016). Auditory perspectives. In B. Nanay (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of perception. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leddington, J. (2014). What we hear. In Brown, R. (Ed.), Consciousness inside and out: Phenomenology, neuroscience, and the nature of experience (pp. 321–334). Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, M. (2005). The labyrinth of time: Introducing the universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1992). Sight and touch. In T. Crane (Ed.), The contents of experience. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (1997). The shallows of the mind. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes, 71, 75–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2007). Perception. In F. Jackson & M. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy, chapter 24 (pp. 701–738). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2012). Sounds and images. The British Journal of Aesthetics., 52(4), 331–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. P. (2005). Seeing, doing, and knowing: A philosophical theory of sense perception. Chicago: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2010). How things look (and what things look that way). In B. Nanay (Ed.), Perceiving the world (pp. 226–253). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2013). Between perception and action. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nudds, M. (2010). What sounds are. In D. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics 5 (pp. 279–302). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Callaghan, C. (2007). Sounds: A philosophical theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Callaghan, C. (2011): Hearing properties, effects, or parts? In Proceedings of the aristotelian society (Vol. 111, No. Part III, 375–405).

  • Parsons, J. (2000). Must a four-dimensionalist believe in temporal parts? The Monist, 83(3), 399–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, J. (2004). Distributional properties. Lewisian themes, 173–80.

  • Paul, L. A. (2010). Temporal experience. The Journal of Philosophy, 107(7), 333–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. (2011). Indiscriminability and experience of change. The Philosophical Quarterly, 61(245), 808–827.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. (2013). Hearing and hallucinating silence. In F. Macpherson & D. Platchias (Eds.), Hallucination (pp. 333–360). Chicago: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prosser, S. (2012). Why does time seem to pass? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85, 92–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rafal, R. (1997). Balint syndrome. In T. Feinberg & M. Farah (Eds.), Behavioral neurology and neuropsychology (pp. 337–356). New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rafal, R. (2003). Balint’s syndrome: a disorder of visual cognition. In M. D’Esposito (Ed.), Neurological foundations of cognitive neuroscience (pp. 27–40). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, L. (2014). Space, time and Molyneux’s question. Ratio, 27(4), 483–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2008). The situation–dependency of perception. The Journal of Philosophy, 105, 55–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2006). On the way things appear. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 461–480). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press on Demand.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2009). The visual experience of causation. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 519–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2015). Objective becoming. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soteriou, M. (2011). The perception of absence, space, and time. In J. Roessler, H. Lerman, & N. Eilan (Eds.), Perception, causation, and objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torrengo, G. (2017). Feeling the passing of time. Journal of Philosophy., 114, 165–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to have received extremely useful comments on the ideas presented in this paper from my colleagues at the Centre for Philosophy of Time at the University of Milan, members of Bence Nanay’s Action and Perception research group at the University of Antwerp, and my audience at the Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society & the Mind Association in July 2016. Particular thanks to Davide Bordini, Clotilde Calabi, Laura Gow, Dave Ingram, Bence Nanay, Matthew Nudds, Casey O’Callaghan, Maarten Steenhagen, and Giuliano Torrengo.

Funding

This study was funded by Università degli Studi di Milano (Project Number 15-6-3007000-2021)

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nick Young.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Young, N. Hearing objects and events. Philos Stud 175, 2931–2950 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0988-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0988-0

Keywords

Navigation