Skip to main content
Log in

Why be a methodological individualist?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the recent methodological individualism-holism debate on explanation, there has been considerable focus on what reasons methodological holists may advance in support of their position. We believe it is useful to approach the other direction and ask what considerations methodological individualists may in fact offer in favor of their view about explanation. This is the background for the question we pursue in this paper: Why be a methodological individualist? We start out by introducing the methodological individualism-holism debate while distinguishing two forms of methodological individualism: a form that says that individualist explanations are always better than holist accounts and a form that says that providing intervening individualist mechanisms always makes for better explanations than purely holist ones. Next, we consider four lines of reasoning in support of methodological individualism: arguments from causation, from explanatory depth, from agency, and from normativity. We argue that none of them offer convincing reasons in support of the two explanatory versions of individualism we consider. While there may well be occasions in which individualists’ favorite explanations are superior, we find no reason to think this always must be the case.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The earliest reference to methodological individualism that we know is Schumpeter (1909).

  2. Recent defenses of methodological holism include (Archer 1995; Elder-Vass 2010; Garfinkel 1981; Hodgson 2007; Jackson and Pettit 1992a, b; Jones 1996; Kincaid 1996, 1997; List and Spiekermann 2013; Sawyer 2002, 2005; Weber and Bouwel 2002). For an overview of the different arguments recently offered in support of methodological holism, see Zahle (2016).

  3. Our main focus is on arguments, both explicit and implied. There are interesting questions about motivations for individualism, where motivations might be broader disciplinary norms and heuristics, for example. Describing those would mean a different project that we cannot pursue here, though our discussion of normative arguments can perhaps be seen in this vain.

  4. We refer to MI2 as the microfoundationalist view. As we spell out the basic claims of this position, it might also be referred to as structural individualism (at least following one common understanding of this notion). On this point see Udehn (2001), but also Demeulenaere (2011).

  5. Accounts of mechanisms may also identify the realizing components of an entity and the activities they enable [see, e.g., Machamer et al. (2000)]. To make the discussion manageable, we focus on MI2 as a claim about intervening variables only.

  6. Schelling was providing “how possibly” models and thus his own commitment to methodological individualism is unclear, yet later commentators certainly have taken his views to support methodological individualism (Raub et al. 2011).

  7. Homans, an early developer of network theory, saw it as an instantiation of methodological individualism (see Freeman 2004) and O’Sullivan and Haklay (2000) confirm the individualist tendencies in contemporary network theory; Epstein (2013), one of the pioneers and leading lights of agent based modeling is quite explicit that the goal is to explain everything in terms of individuals.

  8. Computable general equilibrium models refer to a current set of approaches that model entire economies using almost entirely aggregate variables quantifying over firms, sectors, etc. Even the rather different and much earlier Arrow-Debrieu general equilibrium models quantified over firms and thus were not entirely individualist.

  9. There used to be a common interpretation of Dennett which made him out to be an instrumentalist. That is an interpretation that was shown some time ago to be mistaken by Ross (2000) and explicitly affirmed by Dennett himself (2000) and is fairly explicit in the title of the paper here which is “Real Patterns” and not “Predictively Useful Patterns.”

  10. Ylikoski does not himself endorse the argument. Moreover, he presents a slightly different version of it insofar as he allows that the accounts of the intervening variables may also refer to households and the like. For an account of MI as centered round the idea that individuals are alone in acting by themselves in the social world, see Demeulenaere (2015).

References

  • Archer, M. S. (1995). Realist social theory: The morphogenetic approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2006). The devil in the details: Asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction, and emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayly, S. (2001). Caste, society and politics in India from the eighteenth century to the modern age. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, R. C. (2007). The philosophy of the social sciences. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braybroke, D. (1987). Philosophy of science. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brubaker, R. (2004). Ethnicity without groups. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J. S. (1990). Foundations of social theory. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons, and causes. The Journal of Philosophy, 60(23), 685–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawe, A. (1970). The two sociologies. The British Journal of Sociology, 21(2), 207–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demeulenaere, P. (2011). Introduction. In P. Demeulenaere (Ed.), Analytical sociology and social mechanisms (pp. 1–30). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Demeulenaere, P. (2015). Methodological Individualism: Philosophical Aspects. In J. D. Wright (Ed.), International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences (2nd ed., Vol. 15, pp. 308–313). Oxford: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1989). The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2000). Dennett’s Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment. In D. Ross, D. Thompson, & A. Brook (Eds.), With a little help from my friends (pp. 267–289). Bradford: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Domhoff, G. W. (2014). Who rules america? The triumph of the corporate rich (7th ed.). New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder-Vass, D. (2010). The causal power of social structures. emergence, structure, and agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1983). Explaining technical change: A case study in the philosophy of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, J., & Axtell, R. (1996). Growing artificial societies: Social science from the bottom up. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, J. (2013). Agent zero. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (Or: Disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, L. (2004). The development of social network analysis. Vancouver: Empirical Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, A. (1981). Forms of explanation. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in ethnomethodology. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hannan, M., & Freeman, J. (1989). Organizational ecology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Swedberg, R. (1996). Social mechanisms. Acta Sociologica, 39(3), 281–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, Geoffrey, & Thomson, F. W. (1976). Physicalism: Ontology, determination, and reduction. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 551–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. (2007). Meanings of methodological individualism. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14(2), 211–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollis, M. (1998). The cunning of reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoover, K. (2001). Causality in macroeconomics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, B. (1994). The maxwellians. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, S. (1984). The content of social explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1992a). In defense of explanatory ecumenism. Economics and Philosophy, 8, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1992b). Structural Explanation in Social Theory. In D. Charles & K. Lennon (Eds.), Reduction, explanaiton, and realism (pp. 97–131). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvie, I. C. (1961). Nadel on the aims and methods of social anthropology. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 12(45), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, T. (1996). Methodological individualism in proper perspective. Behavior and Philosophy, 24(2), 119–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Justus, J. (2014). Methodological individualism in ecology. Philosophy of Science, 81, 770–784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1988). Explanatory realism, causal realism, and explanatory exclusion. Midwest Studies, 12(1), 225–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1996). Philosophical foundations of the social sciences. Analyzing controversies in social research. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1997). Individualism and the unity of science: Essays on reduction, explanation, and the special sciences. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (2014). Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate: Essays in the Philosophy of Social Science. In J. Zahle & F. Collin (Eds.), Dead ends and live issues in the individualism-holism debate (pp. 139–152). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (2015). Open empirical and methodological issues in the individualism-holism debate. Philosophy of Science, 82, 1127–1138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (2016). Debating the reality of social classes. Philosophy of The Social Sciences, 46(2), 189–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, P., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency. The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • List, P., & Spiekermann, K. (2013). Methodological individualism and holism in political science: A reconciliation. American Political Science Review, 107(4), 629–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loveman, M. (1999). Is “Race” essential? American Sociological Review, 64(6), 891–898.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lukes, S. (1973). Individualism. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. K., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marchionni, C., & Ylikoski, P. (2013). Generative explanation and individualism in agent-based simulation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 43(3), 323–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massy, D., & Denton, N. (1998). American apartheid: Segregation and the making of the underclass. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1979). The structure of science. Indianapolis: Hacket Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Sullivan, D., & Haklay, M. (2000). Agent based models and individualism. Environment and Planning A, 32, 1409–1425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2009). Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rapport, N. (2017). Being undisciplined: Doing justice to the immensity of human experience. The Sociological Review Monographs, 65(1), 196–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raub, W., Buskens, V., and Van Assen, M. (2011). Micro-macro links in sociology. http//www.tandfonline.com/toc/gmas20/current.

  • Romer, D. (2011). Advanced macroeconomics. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D. (2000). Dennett’s Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment. In D. Ross, D. Thompson, & A. Brook (Eds.), Rainforest realism: A dennettian theory of existence (pp. 147–168). Bradford: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, L. (2016). Game theory in economics and beyond. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 30(4), 107–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, R. K. (2002). Nonreductive individualism: Part I—supervenience and wild disjunction. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 32(4), 537–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, R. K. (2005). Social emergence. Societies as complex systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1969). Models of segregation. American Economic Review, 59(2), 488–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1971). Dynamic models of segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 1(2), 143–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter, J. (1909). On the concept of social value. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 23, 213–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2011). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toumela, R. (2013). Social ontology: Collective intentionality and group agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Udehn, L. (2001). Methodological individualism. Background, history, and meaning. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vercelli, A. (2016). Microfoundations, methodological individualism and alternative economic visions. Review of Political Economy, 28(1), 153–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. W. N. (1957). Historical Explanation in the Social Sciences. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 143–178). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. W. N. (1955). Methodological Individualism: A Reply. In J. O’Neill (Ed.), Modes of individualism and collectivism (pp. 179–184). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wax, M. L. (1980). Paradoxes of “Consent” to the practice of fieldwork. Social Problems, 27(3), 272–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E., & Van Bouwel, J. (2002). Can we dispense with structural explanations of social facts? Economics and Philosophy, 18, 259–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1978). Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology. In G. Roth & C. Wittich eds Trans Ephraim Fishoff et al. Two vols. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Williams, M. (2000). Science and social science. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2005). Making things happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P. (2017). Methodological Individualism. In L. McIntyre & A. Rosenberg (Eds.), The routledge companion to philosophy of social science (pp. 135–146). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, J. (2003). The individualism-holism debate on intertheoretic reduction and the argument from multiple realization. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 33(1), 77–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, J. (2014). Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate: Essays in the Philosophy of Social Science. In J. Zahle & F. Collin (Eds.), Holism, emergence and the crucial distinction (pp. 177–196). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, J. (2016). Methodological Holism in the Social Sciences, In: E.N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/holism-social/.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank the participants at the “1st Bayreuth Workshop in Philosophy of Economics: Explanation in Economics and the Social Sciences” for their helpful comments. Also, thanks to Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Tuukka Kaidesoja, Simon Lohse, Branko Mitrovic, Naftali Weinberger, and two anonymous referees for their useful suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Julie Zahle.

Additional information

Both authors contributed equally to this paper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zahle, J., Kincaid, H. Why be a methodological individualist?. Synthese 196, 655–675 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1523-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1523-8

Keywords

Navigation