Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

How to Interpret Infant Socio-Cognitive Competence

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I review recent evidence that very young, pre-verbal infants attribute belief-like states when anticipating the behavior of others. This evidence is drawn from infant performance on non-verbal false belief tasks. I argue that, contrary to typical interpretations, such evidence does not show that infants attribute belief-like states. Rather, it shows that infants apply an enhanced version of what Gergely (2011) calls the “teleological stance” to brief bouts of behavior. This requires them to parse behavioral sequences into goals and rationally/informationally-constrained means of achieving them; however, it does not require the attribution of unobservable mental states, like beliefs, that are causally responsible for behavior.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. They also make the same judgment of their past selves, denying that they thought the box contained candy prior to opening it, even though this is exactly what they said.

  2. The meta-analysis by Wellman et al. (2001) reviews a wide range of studies that support this timeline in the development of SFBT mastery. This meta-analysis has come under considerable criticism (see Yazdi et al. 2006 for a recent discussion). Also, there is considerable variation in the ages at which children show competence at SFBTs, with some showing such competence long before 4 years of age (Clements and Perner 1994; Carpenter et al. 2002; Happé and Loth 2002). My arguments in what follows are independent of these empirical details.

  3. The scenario with which Onishi and Baillargeon (2005) presented the infants was not precisely the same as in the original Sally-Anne task; I describe it this way only for ease of exposition. The fundamental structure of the scenario was the same, and nothing turns on the differences in details.

  4. Onishi & Baillargeon also ran a true belief version of the task, to make sure that infants do not just look longer, by default, at scenarios where Sally goes to the new toy/candy location. If Sally sees the toy/candy moved, the pattern of results is reversed: they look longer if she subsequently goes to where she left the toy/candy than if she goes to the new location, indicating that they understand that Sally has a true belief about the new location in this condition.

  5. Of course, when it is put this baldly, most researchers impressed with the NVFBT results would adamantly deny this interpretation. However, as I show below, their interpretations of infant performance on NVFBTs often explicitly attribute the capacity to reason about the beliefs, desires and bouts of practical reasoning that animate interpretive targets. Furthermore, all these researchers claim parity between what the SFBTs and the NVFBTs show about understanding belief. So, if one thinks passing SFBTs is the most important milestone in the acquisition of the belief concept, then either one should reject this assumption (as I urge), or one must accept that passing NVFBTs is the most important milestone in the acquisition of the belief concept.

  6. Apperly notes that “in a variety of studies using stories or real objects and using verbal or behavioural judgments, including scenarios where false belief and dual identity problems are very closely matched … the consistent pattern is that children who pass false belief tasks do not necessarily pass such Oedipus problems” (2011, 17). This is in direct conflict with Scott and Baillargeon’s (2009) claim that 18-month-old infants appreciate that others can represent an object—a toy penguin—under a different mode of presentation (as 1-piece rather than 2-piece). I argue below that this is a gross over-interpretation.

  7. I realize that, in one sense, these are not tokens of the same belief type, since my belief is about me and your belief is about you. However, there are other ways of individuating beliefs that are more relevant to action explanation (Perry 1979). The beliefs are of the same type in the sense that they’re both about the agent who tokens them.

  8. Accordingly, an appropriate test for mastery of the belief concept would require children to show some hesitation when attributing beliefs based on limited evidence, and perhaps attempts to find more evidence to rule out competing interpretations.

  9. This does not require the attribution of false beliefs; it is merely a behavioral generalization: if an agent hasn’t witnessed an event relevant to her projects she is not likely to succeed at those projects. Scott & Baillargeon rule this possibility out by running versions of the false belief condition where the penguins are both placed under transparent covers or opaque covers. If infants assume only that ignorant interpretive targets will fail at the task, then this should not affect the results: infants should expect ignorant interpretive targets to select the wrong penguin, even if both are visible or both are invisible. However, this is not what occurs: infants have no expectation that the ignorant interpretive target will select the wrong penguin when both penguins are visible or invisible (Scott and Baillargeon 2009, 1188–1191).

References

  • Apperly, I.A. 2011. Mindreaders. New York: Psychology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I.A., and S.A. Butterfill. 2009. Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychological Review 116(4): 953–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L. 2003. The domain of folk psychology. In Minds and persons, ed. A. O’Hear. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L. 2009. Mindreading in the animal kingdom. In Animal minds, ed. R. Lurz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, D., et al. 2009. Eighteen-month-old infants show false belief understanding in an active helping paradigm. Cognition 112: 337–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., and M. Tomasello. 2008. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12(5): 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter, M., et al. 2002. A new false belief test for 36-month-olds. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 20(3): 393–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, W.A., and J. Perner. 1994. Implicit understanding of belief. Cognitive Development 9(4): 377–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G. 2008. Goal attribution to inanimate agents by 6.5-month-old infants. Cognition 107(70): 705–717.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gergely, G. 2011. Kinds of agents: the origins of understanding instrumental and communicative agency. In Blackwell handbook of childhood cognitive development, 2nd ed, ed. U. Goshwami. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gergely, G., et al. 2002. Rational imitation in preverbal infants. Nature 415: 755.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. 1996. Theories and modules: creation myths, developmental realities, and Neurath’s boat. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers and P. Smith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. 2004. Finding our inner scientist. Daedalus 133: 21–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Happé, F., and E. Loth. 2002. ‘Theory of mind’ and tracking speakers’ intentions. Mind and Language 17(1–2): 24–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. 2008. Folk psychological narratives. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krachun, C., et al. 2009. Can chimpanzees discriminate appearances from reality? Cognition 112: 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. 1988. Infant imitation after a one-week delay: long term memory for novel acts and multiple stimuli. Developmental Psychology 24: 470–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, A. 1996. Folk psychology is not a predictive device. Mind 105(417): 119–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, A. 2003. The importance of being understood. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K., and R. Baillargeon. 2005. Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science 308: 255–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. 1979. The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs 13: 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R., and R. Baillargeon. 2009. Which penguin is this? Attributing false beliefs about object identity at 18 months. Child Development 80(4): 1172–1196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Song, H., et al. 2008. Can an actor’s false belief be corrected by an appropriate communication? Psychological reasoning in 18.5-month-old infants. Cognition 109: 295–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Surian, L., et al. 2007. Attribution of beliefs by 13-month-old infants. Psychological Science 18: 580–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H., et al. 2001. Metaanalysis of theory-of-mind development: the truth about false belief. Child Development 72: 655–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yazdi, A.A., et al. 2006. Competence and performance in belief-desire reasoning across two cultures: the truth, the whole truth and nothing but the truth about false belief? Cognition 100: 343–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tadeusz Wieslaw Zawidzki.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Zawidzki, T.W. How to Interpret Infant Socio-Cognitive Competence. Rev.Phil.Psych. 2, 483–497 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0064-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0064-1

Keywords

Navigation