Skip to main content
Log in

Absolutism About Taste and Faultless Disagreement

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is usually claimed that taste utterances have judge-dependent semantic content. Jeremy Wyatt recently proposed a semantic theory that rejects this claim. According to him, the semantic content of taste sentences is judge-independent, but the content of our assertions made by uttering taste sentences is judge-dependent. He showed that this account explains faultless disagreements about tastes. My paper aims to raise some challenges to his proposal. First, a judge-independent taste proposition semantically expressed by a taste sentence seems unrelated to a judge-dependent taste proposition asserted by the speaker. It means that the latter proposition is not systematically obtained from the former. Second, the theory assumes that there are judge-independent taste properties (like being tasty, full stop). The existence of such properties can be questioned because it is problematic to state instantiation conditions for them. The paper ends with a sketch of an alternative explanation; it shares Wyatt’s account of faultless disagreements but does not suffer from its drawbacks.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The idea that disagreements about matters of personal taste can be faultless seems to be less controversial than the idea that disagreements about moral and aesthetic issues can be faultless. If there are facts of ethics and aesthetics “out there,” disagreements in these domains might not be faultless. Nevertheless, there are attempts to show otherwise—see, e.g., Hills (2013) for a theory of faultless moral disagreements and Baker and Robson (2017), McIver Lopes (2017), and Schafer (2011) for theories of faultless aesthetic disagreements.

  2. Versions of relativism have been proposed in, e.g., Egan (2014), Kölbel (2002, 2004), Lasersohn (2005), MacFarlane (2005, 2014), Richard (2008), Stephenson (2007), and Wright (1992, 2008).

  3. The labels “faultless intuition” and “disagreement intuition” are Clapp’s (see Clapp 2015, pp. 520–521).

  4. Versions of contextualism have been proposed in, e.g., Cappelen and Hawthorne (2009), Glanzberg (2007), and Recanati (2007) (see also references in footnote 6).

  5. Recently, Raven (2017, p. 169) argued that relativism joins contextualism because it also fails to preserve the disagreement intuition. The same would hold if contextualism and relativism were mere notational variants (see Stojanovic 2007). Independently of the relativism vs. contextualism debate, also Moltmann (2010, pp. 194–195) blamed the former for the failure to explain taste disagreements. MacFarlane (2014, pp. 118–137) defends the view that relativism fares better than contextualism (and other approaches on the market) in explaining taste disagreements.

  6. See, e.g., Barker (2013), Buekens (2011), Gutzmann (2016), Huvenes (2014), López de Sa (2008, 2015), Marques and García-Carpintero (2014), Plunkett and Sundell (2013), Silk (2016), Sundell (2011), and Zouhar (2018). Zeman (2017) summarizes contextualist attempts to preserve the disagreement intuition.

  7. See Baker and Robson (2017), Hills (2013), Schafer (2011), and Wyatt (2018). An interesting addition to this literature is Hirvonen (2016) in which absolutism is defended for the so-called objectivist uses of taste predicates that are based on a folk theory of taste. For criticisms of Schafer (2011), see Eriksson and Tiozzo (2016).

  8. Given that J1 and J2 are judges, J1’s attitude A1 is non-cotenable with J2’s attitude A2 provided J1 could not coherently adopt A2 without changing her mind (and mutatis mutandis for J2) (see MacFarlane 2014, p. 121).

  9. The discussion in this section shows that judge-dependent taste propositions asserted or believed by speakers are not systematically obtained from judge-independent taste propositions that are supposed to be semantically expressed by uttered taste sentences. Interestingly, David Lewis (1980, pp. 93–94) admitted that semantic values and propositional contents of sentences in contexts may come apart, but still insisted that the assignment of the former should determine the assignment of the latter (see Yalcin 2014 for a detailed discussion about the distinction between semantic value and content). Lewis thus required that there must be a systematic relation between semantic value and content. Wyatt’s attempt to combine both judge-dependent and judge-independent taste proposition in a single picture can be described as sinning against an analogous requirement. I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer for the suggestion to frame the present discussion in this way.

  10. Cappelen and Lepore’s version of semantic minimalism differs from Borg’s. It admits that the semantic contents of sentences may vary relative to contexts of utterance provided they contain explicit indexicals; see Cappelen and Lepore (2005).

  11. This holds in ordinary cases in which utterances of “This is tasty” license the so-called acquaintance inference, i.e., the inference from an utterance of “This is tasty” to “The speaker has tasted this” (assuming, of course, that the two occurrences of “this” are co-referential) (see Ninan 2014, p. 292). In ordinary cases, if an utterance of “This is tasty” fails to license the acquaintance inference, the utterance is infelicitous. It should be recognized, however, that there are special uses of “This is tasty” that do not license the acquaintance inference. They include, for example, exocentric uses, uses embedded in conditionals, and uses featuring epistemic modals (see Ninan 2014, p. 299). Furthermore, notice that, in some exceptional situations, one can be entitled to utter “This is tasty, but not to me” (see Anthony 2016, Sc. 2.2 for a detailed discussion). In such cases, Ann’s utterance of “This is tasty” could be true but the proposition that B’s flavor is pleasing to Ann’s tastes would be false. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this point.

  12. It is sometimes claimed that the business of semanticists is independent of the business of metaphysicians (see, e.g., Cappelen and Lepore 2005, Ch. 11). I disagree. If it turned out that, besides judge-dependent taste properties, there is no judge-independent taste property, an absolutist semantics for taste predicates would be a non-starter. The metaphysics of properties should thus tell us whether taste absolutism can be put on a firm footing.

  13. Two properties of being salty can be distinguished, namely chemical and gustatory. I have in mind here the former property, as objects instantiate it merely on the basis of its chemical composition. The gustatory property of being salty requires an appeal to a judge in the same way as being too salty and being tasty.

  14. It might be admitted that there is more than one ideal judge, but in such a case all ideal judges should make the same decisions about the same flavors.

  15. In fact, the account in Zouhar (2018) is slightly different. It is claimed there that the property of being tasty for someone is nothing but the property of interacting with someone’s gustatory capacities in a way that produces agreeable gustatory experiences of an intrinsically desirable sort. This explication was inspired by Egan’s dispositional account proposed in Egan (2010). It is rather widespread to treat judge-dependent properties as dispositional, modeled on Lewis’s dispositional theory of values from Lewis (1989) (see also Clapp 2015; López de Sa 2017; Marques 2016). My reasons for rejecting the dispositional part are given in Zouhar (2018). Some considerations in Ninan (2014) also can be understood as casting doubts on dispositional accounts of taste properties.

  16. This is a simplified version of the definition from Duží et al. (2010, p. 361).

References

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer for Acta Analytica for her or his criticisms and useful suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marián Zouhar.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that she has no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zouhar, M. Absolutism About Taste and Faultless Disagreement. Acta Anal 35, 273–288 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-019-00409-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-019-00409-w

Keywords

Navigation