Stoicism

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Stoicism was one of the new philosophical movements of the Hellenistic period. The name derives from the porch (stoa poikilê) in the Agora at Athens decorated with mural paintings, where the members of the school congregated, and their lectures were held. Unlike ‘epicurean,’ the sense of the English adjective ‘stoical’ is not utterly misleading with regard to its philosophical origins. The Stoics did, in fact, hold that emotions like fear or envy (or impassioned sexual attachments, or passionate love of anything whatsoever) either were, or arose from, false judgements and that the sage—a person who had attained moral and intellectual perfection—would not undergo them. The later Stoics of Roman Imperial times, Seneca and Epictetus, emphasise the doctrines (already central to the early Stoics' teachings) that the sage is utterly immune to misfortune and that virtue is sufficient for happiness. Our phrase ‘stoic calm’ perhaps encapsulates the general drift of these claims. It does not, however, hint at the even more radical ethical views which the Stoics defended, e.g. that only the sage is free while all others are slaves, or that all those who are morally vicious are equally so. Though it seems clear that some Stoics took a kind of perverse joy in advocating views which seem so at odds with common sense, they did not do so simply to shock. Stoic ethics achieves a certain plausibility within the context of their physical theory and psychology, and within the framework of Greek ethical theory as that was handed down to them from Plato and Aristotle. It seems that they were well aware of the mutually interdependent nature of their philosophical views, likening philosophy itself to a living animal in which logic is bones and sinews; ethics and physics, the flesh and the soul respectively (another version reverses this assignment, making ethics the..

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 106,314

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

A new stoicism.Paula Gottlieb - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (1):92-94.
Stoicism & emotion.Margaret Graver - 2007 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Stoicism: Traditions and Transformations.Steven K. Strange & Jack Zupko (eds.) - 2004 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Stoicism Today.Jean-Baptiste Gourinat - 2009 - Iris. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate 1 (2):497-511.
Cynicism and stoicism.Christopher Gill - 2013 - In Roger Crisp, The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stoicism and Food.William O. Stephens - 2018 - Encyclopedia of Food and Agricultural Ethics.
Stoicism, Feminism and Autonomy.Scott Aikin & Emily McGill-Rutherford - 2014 - Symposion: Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences 1 (1):9-22.
A New Stoicism. [REVIEW]Geoffrey M. Batchelder - 2000 - Review of Metaphysics 53 (4):915-917.
Stoicism and emotion (review).James Warren - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (4):pp. 633-634.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
1,524 (#11,626)

6 months
159 (#31,463)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Dirk Baltzly
University of Tasmania

Citations of this work

On being attached.Monique Wonderly - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (1):223-242.
Moral intuitionism and disagreement.Brian Besong - 2014 - Synthese 191 (12):2767-2789.
Free Will and the Bounds of the Self.Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols - 2001 - In Robert Kane, The Oxford Handbook of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.

View all 28 citations / Add more citations