On There Being Infinitely Many Thinkable Thoughts: A Reply to Porpora and a Defence of Tegmark

Philosophia 43 (1):35-42 (2015)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Porpora offers an a priori argument for the conclusion that there are infinitely many thoughts that it is physically possible for us to think. That there should be such an a priori argument is astonishing enough. That the argument should be simple enough to teach to a first-year undergraduate class in about 20 min, as Porpora’s is, is more astonishing still. Porpora’s main target is Max Tegmark’s recent argument for the claim that if current physics is right, then there are mental duplicates of us in far flung regions of the Universe. His argument is directed against Tegmark’s assumption that mental facts supervene upon physical facts. So, if Porpora’s argument is sound then not only is Tegmark’s argument unsound, but physicalism is also false. So, Porpora’s argument is powerful indeed. Who would have thought that a simple a priori argument, together with the physical facts, could solve the issue of whether physicalism is true?. Not I. In this paper I take a closer look at Porpora’s argument and show that it is fallacious. I also consider the other reasons Porpora gives for thinking there are infinitely many thinkable thoughts and find them similarly lacking

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Operant conditioning and a paradox of teleology.Jon Ringen - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (4):565-577.
Is the Universe Really That Simple?Milan M. Ćirković - 2002 - Foundations of Physics 32 (7):1141-1157.
Four concepts of social structure Douglas V. Porpora.Douglas V. Porpora - 1989 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 19 (2):195–211.
Philosophical implications of inflationary cosmology.Joshua Knobe, Ken D. Olum & And Alexander Vilenkin - 2006 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57 (1):47-67.
On Simple Facts.M. Oreste Fiocco - 2014 - Res Philosophica 91 (3):287-313.
The overdetermination argument revisited.Agustín Vicente - 2004 - Minds and Machines 14 (3):331-47.
Epistemological physicalism and the knowledge argument.Jesper Kallestrup - 2006 - American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (1):1-23.
In defense of wordless thoughts about thoughts.Robert W. Lurz - 2007 - Mind and Language 22 (3):270–296.
A defence of the explanatory argument for physicalism.Jared Bates - 2009 - Philosophical Quarterly 59 (235):315-324.
Trinity and creation: Why Kortum's argument fails.Tom Mccall - 2007 - Heythrop Journal 48 (2):260–266.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-11-27

Downloads
84 (#196,609)

6 months
11 (#222,787)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Benjamin L. Curtis
Nottingham Trent University

References found in this work

The meaning of 'meaning'.Hilary Putnam - 1975 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7:131-193.
New work for a theory of universals.David K. Lewis - 1983 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (4):343-377.
New Work For a Theory of Universals.David Lewis - 1983 - In D. H. Mellor & Alex Oliver (eds.), Properties. Oxford University Press.
The semantic paradoxes: A diagnostic investigation.Charles Chihara - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (4):590-618.
The semantic paradoxes: Some second thoughts.Charles Chihara - 1984 - Philosophical Studies 45 (2):223 - 229.

View all 8 references / Add more references