Unity of Reasons

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (4):877-895 (2016)
Abstract
There are at least two basic normative notions: rationality and reasons. The dominant normative account of reasons nowadays, which I call primitive pluralism about reasons, holds that some reasons are normatively basic and there is no underlying normative explanation of them in terms of other normative notions. Kantian constructivism about reasons, understood as a normative rather than a metaethical view, holds that rationality is the primitive normative notion that picks out which non-normative facts are reasons for what and explains why those normative relations hold. By supposing that there is a plurality of primitive reasons, I argue that primitive pluralism about reasons lacks sufficient normative unity and structure. But Kantian constructivism about reasons faces a dilemma of its own: Either a conception of rationality is thick enough to capture the reasons of commonsense, in which case it cannot play the explanatory role assigned to it, or a conception of rationality is genuinely explanatory, in which case it is too thin to generate the reasons we recognize in commonsense. The aim of this paper is to suggest that if Kantian constructivism about reasons were built on a substantive, rather than merely formal, conception of rationality then it would stand a better chance at unifying the particular reasons we would endorse on due reflection. The groundwork I lay in this paper, I explain, is an essential first step in the larger project of developing a version of Kantian constructivism about reasons that might eventually explain all reasons in terms of rationality
Keywords Kantian constructivism  Rationality  Reasons  Scanlon
Categories (categorize this paper)
DOI 10.1007/s10677-016-9704-y
Options
 Save to my reading list
Follow the author(s)
Edit this record
My bibliography
Export citation
Find it on Scholar
Mark as duplicate
Request removal from index
Revision history
Download options
Our Archive


Upload a copy of this paper     Check publisher's policy     Papers currently archived: 29,848
External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server
Configure custom proxy (use this if your affiliation does not provide a proxy)
Through your library
References found in this work BETA
Ethics Without Principles.Jonathan Dancy - 2004 - Oxford University Press.
Why Be Rational?Niko Kolodny - 2005 - Mind 114 (455):509-563.
Political Liberalism.J. Rawls - 1995 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 57 (3):596-598.
What We Owe to Each Other.Thomas Scanlon - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):323-354.
Constructivism About Reasons.Sharon Street - 2008 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 3:207-45.

View all 18 references / Add more references

Citations of this work BETA

No citations found.

Add more citations

Similar books and articles
Sources, Reasons, and Requirements.Bruno Guindon - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (5):1253-1268.
Normative Requirements.John Broome - 1999 - Ratio 12 (4):398–419.
Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality.Jonathan Way - 2009 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy.
Parfit's Challenges.Marko Jurjako - 2011 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):237-248.
Reasons and Normativity in Critical Thinking.Guðmundur Heiðar Frímannsson - 2016 - Studier I Pædagogisk Filosofi 4 (1):3-16.
Kantian Reasons for Reasons.Noell Birondo - 2007 - Ratio 20 (3):264–277.
Why Be Rational?Niko Kolodny - 2005 - Mind 114 (455):509-563.
Knowledge, Explanation, and Motivating Reasons.Dustin Locke - forthcoming - American Philosophical Quarterly.
Reasons, Values, and Rational Actions.Paul K. Moser - 1990 - Journal of Philosophical Research 15:127-151.
What Apparent Reasons Appear to Be.Kurt Sylvan - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (3):587-606.
Added to PP index
2016-02-25

Total downloads
24 ( #230,461 of 2,210,513 )

Recent downloads (6 months)
6 ( #82,093 of 2,210,513 )

How can I increase my downloads?

Monthly downloads
My notes
Sign in to use this feature