The not-so-sweet science: the role of the medical profession in boxing

Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (5):513-514 (2004)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The medical profession’s role should be limited to advice and informationThe medical establishment’s desire to interfere with the autonomous wishes of boxers seems at odds with the principle of respect for autonomy prevalent in contemporary biomedical practice. I argue that the role of the medical profession in boxing should be solely an advisory and informational one. In addition, the distinctions made between boxing and other high risk sports often rely on an insufficient knowledge of the sport. This leads to misdirected criticisms and excessive emphasis on the colourful discourse of boxing, as opposed to the practice of boxing itself. Dr Herrera’s claim in his article that boxing differs from other sports in the acceptability of its acts outside the realm of sport is refuted.1 The importance of consent as a legitimising factor is highlighted, and a number of possible solutions to improve safety within the sport are tentatively suggested.In the United Kingdom, a competent adult may legally refuse medical treatment, irrespective of the severity of his condition or the validity of his reasons. With the pre-eminence of an autonomy based model of bioethics, respecting a patient’s wishes forms an integral part of acting in his best interests. It is puzzling, then, to find that the Australian Medical Association have called for a ban on boxing on the grounds that the activity is excessively hazardous to the health of boxers. The often mentioned principle of respect for autonomy is abandoned once the person drops the privileged title of “patient”. This suggests that being a patient …

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,219

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Medicine and sociology: A parting of the ways.John E. Thomas - 1981 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 6 (4):411-422.
Collective responsibility and the practice of medicine.Peter A. French - 1982 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 7 (1):65-86.
Physiology, hygiene and the entry of women to the medical profession in edinburgh C. 1869-c. 1900.E. Thomson - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 32 (1):105-126.
Boxing clever.P. D. Toon - 1988 - Journal of Medical Ethics 14 (2):69-69.
Euthanasia in The Netherlands: The Role of the Dutch Medical Profession.R. J. M. Dillmann - 1996 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 5 (1):100.
What can we learn by looking for the first code of professional ethics?Michael Davis - 2003 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24 (5):433-454.
A short history of medical ethics.Albert R. Jonsen - 2000 - New York: Oxford University press.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-08-24

Downloads
94 (#176,872)

6 months
4 (#698,851)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Thinking outside the Ring of Concussive Punches: Reimagining Boxing.Joseph Lee - 2021 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 16 (4):413-426.
Meaning and morality in boxing.Michael-John Turp - forthcoming - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy:1-15.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Out for the count.Mark Johnson - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):589-589.

Add more references