Using the family covenant in planning end-of-life care: Obligations and promises of patients, families, and physicians
Abstract
Physicians and families need to interact more meaningfully to clarify the values and preferences at stake in advance care planning. The current use of advance directives fails to respect patient autonomy. This paper proposes using the family covenant as a preventive ethics process designed to improve end-of-life planning by incorporating other family members—as agreed to by the patient and those family members—into the medical care dialogue. The family covenant formulates advance directives in conversation with family members and with the assistance of a physician, thereby making advance directives more acceptable to the family, and more intelligible to other physicians. It adds the moral force of a promise to the obligation of respecting a patient’s preferences about end-of-life care. These negotiations between patient, family, and physician, from early planning phases through implementation, should greatly reduce the incidence of family disagreements on what the patient would have wanted. The family covenant ensures advance directive discussions within the family, promotes and respects the autonomy of other family members, and might even spur others in the family to complete advance directives through additional covenants. The family covenant holds the potential to transform moral quagmires into meaningful moral conversation. J Am Geriatr Soc 51:1155–1158, 2003.My notes
Similar books and articles
Family Physicians and the Family Covenant Model's Usefulness in Solving Genetic Testing Conflicts.Ray Moseley - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (3):28-29.
The family covenant and genetic testing.David J. Doukas & Jessica W. Berg - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (3):2 – 10.
The patient in the family and the family in the patient.Barry Hoffmaster & Wayne Weston - 1987 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 8 (3).
The value history: A necessary family document.Renate G. Justin - 1987 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 8 (3).
Too soon to give up: Re-examining the value of advance directives.Benjamin H. Levi & Michael J. Green - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (4):3 – 22.
Observations of physician, patient and family perceptions of informed consent in Houston, texas.Eugene V. Boisaubin - 2004 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 29 (2):225 – 236.
Advance directives in patients with Alzheimer's disease; Ethical and clinical considerations.J. Vollmann - 2001 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 4 (2):161-167.
Analytics
Added to PP
2009-01-28
Downloads
47 (#251,171)
6 months
1 (#450,425)
2009-01-28
Downloads
47 (#251,171)
6 months
1 (#450,425)
Historical graph of downloads
Citations of this work
The near-failure of advance directives: why they should not be abandoned altogether, but their role radically reconsidered.Marta Spranzi & Véronique Fournier - 2016 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 19 (4):563-568.
Ethical Quandaries in Gamete-Embryo Cryopreservation Related to Oncofertility.Leslie Ayensu-Coker, Ellen Essig, Lesley L. Breech & Steven Lindheim - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (3):711-719.
References found in this work
The family covenant and genetic testing.David J. Doukas & Jessica W. Berg - 2001 - American Journal of Bioethics 1 (3):2 – 10.
Preventive ethics: expanding the horizons of clinical ethics.Lachlan Forrow, Robert M. Arnold & Lisa S. Parker - 1993 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 4 (4):287.
Living wills and substituted judgments: A critical analysis.Jos V. M. Welie - 2001 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 4 (2):169-183.
The problem of proxies with interests of their own: toward a better theory of proxy decisions.J. Hardwig - 1992 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 4 (1):20-27.
Comparison of patients' and health care professionals' attitudes towards advance directives.D. Blondeau, P. Valois, E. W. Keyserlingk, M. Hebert & M. Lavoie - 1998 - Journal of Medical Ethics 24 (5):328-335.