Cut as Consequence

History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (4):349-379 (2010)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The papers where Gerhard Gentzen introduced natural deduction and sequent calculi suggest that his conception of logic differs substantially from the now dominant views introduced by Hilbert, Gödel, Tarski, and others. Specifically, (1) the definitive features of natural deduction calculi allowed Gentzen to assert that his classical system nk is complete based purely on the sort of evidence that Hilbert called ?experimental?, and (2) the structure of the sequent calculi li and lk allowed Gentzen to conceptualize completeness as a question about the relationships among a system's individual rules (as opposed to the relationship between a system as a whole and its ?semantics?). Gentzen's conception of logic is compelling in its own right. It is also of historical interest, because it allows for a better understanding of the invention of natural deduction and sequent calculi.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 97,060

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-10-29

Downloads
92 (#192,801)

6 months
16 (#285,856)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Curtis Franks
University of Notre Dame

Citations of this work

The Deduction Theorem (Before and After Herbrand).Curtis Franks - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 42 (2):129-159.
Necessity of Thought.Cesare Cozzo - 2014 - In Heinrich Wansing (ed.), Dag Prawitz on Proofs and Meaning. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. pp. 101-20.
Early Structural Reasoning. Gentzen 1932.Enrico Moriconi - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (4):662-679.
Rule-Irredundancy and the Sequent Calculus for Core Logic.Neil Tennant - 2016 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (1):105-125.
The Context of Inference.Curtis Franks - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (4):365-395.

View all 7 citations / Add more citations