Early Science and Medicine 18 (4-5):405-434 (2013)

Abstract
Francis Bacon’s elusive notion of experience can be better understood when we relate it to his views on matter, motion, appetite and intellect, and bring to the fore its broader philosophical implications. Bacon’s theory of knowledge is embedded in a programme of disciplinary redefinition, outlined in the Advancement of Learning and De augmentis scientiarum. Among all disciplines, prima philosophia plays a key foundational role, based on the idea of both a physical parallelism between the human intellect and nature and a theological parallelism between nature and God. Failure to assess Bacon’s distinctive position concerning the way in which the mind mirrors both the natural and the divine world, that is to say, the meaning of “reality,” has resulted in notoriously jejune discussions on Baconian empiricism, monotonously driven by epistemological concerns. As a result, the standard view on Bacon’s empiricism is as epistemologically comforting as it is imaginary, an “idol” in a genuinely Baconian sense. In this article, Bacon’s notion of experience will be discussed by examining those steps that he considered to be the crucial initial stages in the formation of human experience, stages described as a process of experiential literacy or, in emblematic terms, as a hunting expedition led by the mythological figure of Pan. I argue that a well-rounded analysis of Bacon’s experientia literata needs to take into account the complementary notion of the “spelling-book of nature”, that is, the original code of the primordial motions of matter. By getting acquainted with the first rudiments of experience through its spelling-book, one learns to read the book of nature and, most of all, to write new pages in it.
Keywords No keywords specified (fix it)
Categories (categorize this paper)
DOI 10.1163/15733823-1845p0005
Options
Edit this record
Mark as duplicate
Export citation
Find it on Scholar
Request removal from index
Revision history

Download options

PhilArchive copy


Upload a copy of this paper     Check publisher's policy     Papers currently archived: 51,480
External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server
Configure custom proxy (use this if your affiliation does not provide a proxy)
Through your library

References found in this work BETA

Introduction.Amanda Rees - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Science 49 (3):383-386.

Add more references

Citations of this work BETA

Add more citations

Similar books and articles

God and Nature: Is the Divorce Final?Leslie Armour - 2007 - Maritain Studies/Etudes Maritainiennes 23:3 - 24.
Philosophical Accounts of Learning.Paul Hager - 2005 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 (5):649–666.
Towards a Theory of Learning.Stewart Ranson, Jane Martin, Jon Nixon & Penny McKeown - 1996 - British Journal of Educational Studies 44 (1):9 - 26.
Learning How to Learn: A Critique.Christopher Winch - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 42 (3-4):649-665.
Reading the Bible and Learning to Read.Joseph T. Lienhard - 1996 - Augustinian Studies 27 (1):7-25.
Learning to Read Nietzsche.Maudemarie Clark - 2001 - International Studies in Philosophy 33 (3):53-64.
The Role of Pictures in Learning to Read.Douglas P. Newton - 1995 - Educational Studies 21 (1):119-130.

Analytics

Added to PP index
2013-12-23

Total views
12 ( #719,055 of 2,330,621 )

Recent downloads (6 months)
1 ( #585,854 of 2,330,621 )

How can I increase my downloads?

Downloads

My notes