Recent work on Kantian maxims I: Established approaches
Philosophy Compass 5 (3):216-227 (2010)
Abstract
Maxims play a crucial role in Kant's ethical philosophy, but there is significant disagreement about what maxims are. In this two-part essay, I survey eight different views of Kantian maxims, presenting their strengths, and their weaknesses. Part I: Established Approaches, begins with Rüdiger Bubner's view that Kant took maxims to be what ordinary people of today take them to be, namely pithily expressed precepts of morality or prudence. Next comes the position, most associated with Rüdiger Bittner and Otfried Höffe, that maxims are Lebensregeln, or 'life-rules'– quite general rules for how to conduct oneself based on equally general outlooks on how the world is. These first two interpretations make sense of Kant's claim, made in his anthropological and pedagogical writings, that we have to learn how to act on maxims, but they become less plausible in light of Kant's probable view that people always act on maxims – after all, how can people learn how to act on something they always act on anyway? The next two views, each advanced, at different times, by Onora O'Neill, make better sense of the fact that people always act on maxims, for they hold that maxims are intentions – either specific intentions, such as 'to open the door', or general intentions, such as 'to make guests feel welcome'– and it is perfectly sensible to claim that people always act on intentions. However, they face the same problem as the two previous views, which is that if people always act on maxims, what sense does it make to say they also have to learn how to act on them? Henry Allison, the main representative of the fifth view, claims, on the basis of Kant's doctrine of the 'highest maxim', that maxims are principles organized hierarchically, such that an agent endorses one maxim because she endorses a more general maxim. Unfortunately for Allison, there is little direct textual support for his claim that maxims are organized hierarchically.Author's Profile
DOI
10.1111/j.1747-9991.2009.00254.x
My notes
Similar books and articles
Quantity, volubility, and some varieties of discourse.Mitchell S. Green - 1995 - Linguistics and Philosophy 18 (1):83 - 112.
Maxims in Kant's practical philosophy.Richard R. McCarty - 2006 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (1):65-83.
Rethinking our maxims: Perceptual salience and practical judgment in Kantian ethics.Talbot Brewer - 2001 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4 (3):219-230.
The Book of Jewish Wisdom: The Talmud of the Well-Considered Life.Jacob Neusner & Noam Mordecai Menahem Neusner (eds.) - 1996 - Continuum.
The Life and Maxims of Ske̳nde̳s.Claude Sumner - 1981 - Printed for the Ministry of Culture and Sports by Commercial Printing Press.
Analytics
Added to PP
2010-03-16
Downloads
140 (#91,334)
6 months
2 (#299,341)
2010-03-16
Downloads
140 (#91,334)
6 months
2 (#299,341)
Historical graph of downloads
Author's Profile
Citations of this work
Kant’s Account of Epistemic Normativity.Reza Hadisi - forthcoming - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
Practical judgment as reflective judgment: On moral salience and Kantian particularist universalism.Sabina Vaccarino Bremner - forthcoming - European Journal of Philosophy.
Schizophrenia and Moral Responsibility: A Kantian Essay.Matthé Scholten - 2016 - Philosophia 44 (1):205-225.
References found in this work
Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy.Onora O'Neill - 1989 - Cambridge University Press.