Practical Reasoning and the First Person

Philosophia 45 (2):677-700 (2017)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

I argue that while practical reasoning is essentially first personal it does not require having essentially first personal thoughts. I start with an example of good practical reasoning. Because there is debate about what practical reasoning is, I discuss how different sides in those debates can accommodate my example. I then consider whether my example involves essentially first personal thoughts. It is not always clear what philosophers who would claim that it must have in mind. I identify two features of essentially personal thoughts that they share with their impersonal counterparts: they have the same truth conditions and can have the same evidential bases. I next argue that my example of good practical reasoning does not involve any thoughts other than the impersonal ones of the kind I identified. I defend this conclusion against several objections. One pair of objections starts from claims to the effect that there can be no difference in two people’s actions, or in the reasons they have, without a difference in their beliefs or desires. I argue that these claims are false. I then consider an alleged skeptical possibility that often motivates the idea that practical reasoning requires special first personal beliefs. I conclude the paper by suggesting that what Anscombe called an ‘overly contemplative’ conception of knowledge and belief encourages this skeptical possibility. If we think of having a belief as like having a map of the world, then we will easily think that we need self-locating beliefs the way we need ‘I am here’ stickers on maps. The best response, I suggest, is to reject the image that beliefs are like maps.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,423

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Knowledge and Practical Reasoning.Igor Douven - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (1):101-118.
Knowledge and practical reasoning.Igor Douven - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (1):101–118.
What is (Correct) Practical Reasoning?Julian Fink - 2013 - Acta Analytica 28 (4):471-482.
Why Intentions?Jesse M. Mulder - 2016 - Ratio 31 (S1):51-64.
Practical Reasoning.Bart Streumer - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), Blackwell Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 244-251.
Pollock on Practical Reasoning.David Hitchcock - 2002 - Informal Logic 22 (3).
Truth, Lies, and Good Reasons.Brian Douglas Huss - 2002 - Dissertation, University of Minnesota
Reason and experience.Kurt Baier - 1973 - Noûs 7 (1):56-67.
Is there an epistemic norm of practical reasoning?Davide Fassio - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (9):2137-2166.
Practical aspects of theoretical reasoning.Gilbert Harman - 2004 - In Piers Rawling & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 45--56.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-04-22

Downloads
39 (#399,999)

6 months
12 (#202,587)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

David Hunter
Toronto Metropolitan University

References found in this work

Rationality Through Reasoning.John Broome (ed.) - 2013 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Intention.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1957 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy.Bernard Williams - 1985 - Cambridge, Mass.: Routledge.
Attitudes de dicto and de se.David Lewis - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (4):513-543.

View all 36 references / Add more references