The Incompatibility of Omniscience and Intentional Action: A Reply to David P. Hunt: Tomis Kapitan

Religious Studies 30 (1):55-66 (1994)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In ‘Omniprescient Agency’ David P. Hunt challenges an argument against the possibility of an omniscient agent. The argument – my own in ‘Agency and Omniscience’ – assumes that an agent is a being capable of intentional action, where, minimally, an action is intentional only if it is caused, in part, by the agent's intending. The latter, I claimed, is governed by a psychological principle of ‘least effort’, namely, that no one intends without antecedently feeling that deliberate effort is needed to achieve desired goals, such effort has a chance of success, and it is yet contingent whether the effort will be expended and the goals realized. The goals can be anything from immediate intentional doings, tryings or basic actions, to remote and perhaps unlikely consequences of actions, e.g. global justice. The thrust of the principle is that it would be impossible for a wholly rational self-aware agent to intend without a background presumption of an open future as concerns the desired state and the means to it. But this presumption embodies a sense of contingency which, in turn, requires an acknowledged ignorance about what the future holds, otherwise the future would appear closed relative to present knowledge with the desired state presented as either guaranteed or ruled out . Regardless whether this self-directed attitude is accurate, it follows that intentional action precludes complete knowledge of one's present and future. Consequently, no omniscient or omniprescient being can be an agent

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Weakness of Will as a Problem for Practical Rationality.Keith David Wyma - 1997 - Dissertation, University of Notre Dame
Shared intention and the doxastic single end condition.Olle Blomberg - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (2):351-372.
Agent Causation and Acting for Reasons.Rebekah L. H. Rice - 2011 - American Philosophical Quarterly 48 (4):333-346.
The Phenomenology of Freedom.Tomis Kapitan - 2007 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 28 (3/4):189.
Unconscious vision and the platitudes of folk psychology.Cara Spencer - 2007 - Philosophical Psychology 20 (3):309 – 327.
The Guise of the Good.J. David Velleman - 1992 - Noûs 26 (1):3 - 26.
Ramsey's Principle Re-situated.Jérôme Dokic & Pascal Engel - 2004 - In Hallvard Lillehammer & D. H. Mellor (eds.), Ramsey's Legacy. Oxford University Press.
Skill, luck, control, and intentional action.Thomas Nadelhoffer - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (3):341 – 352.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-02-05

Downloads
27 (#574,515)

6 months
3 (#992,474)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Tomis Kapitan
Indiana University, Bloomington (PhD)

Citations of this work

The freedom of Christ and the problem of deliberation.Timothy Pawl - 2014 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 75 (3):233-247.
Against Deliberation Restrictions.Garrett Pendergraft - 2014 - Religious Studies 50 (3):341-357.
Counterfactuals of divine freedom.Yishai Cohen - 2016 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 79 (3):185-205.
The Freedom of Christ and Explanatory Priority.Timothy Pawl - 2014 - Religious Studies 50 (2):157-173.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind.John R. Searle - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Intention, plans, and practical reason.Michael Bratman - 1987 - Cambridge: Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Intentionality.John Searle - 1983 - Philosophy 59 (229):417-418.
A Theory of Human Action.Alvin Ira Goldman - 1970 - Englewood Cliffs, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.

View all 13 references / Add more references