Some ethical implications of practicing philosophy with children and adults

Childhood and Philosophy 17:01-16 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This paper acts as an introduction to a dossier centered on the ethical implications of Practicing Philosophy with Children and Adults. It identifies ethical themes in the P4C movement over three generations of theorists and practitioners, and argues that, historically and materially, the transition to a “new” hermeneutics of childhood that has occurred within the P4C movement may be said to have emerged as a response to the ever-increasing pressure of neoliberalism and a weaponized capitalism to construct public policies in education on an over-regulated, prescribed, state-monitored, model. Could a new relationship to childhood provide the ethical and political agenda that our times require for doing philosophy with children with integrity? Could a radical listening and openness to childhood—which has been an intrinsic confessional characteristic of P4C pedagogy from the beginning--sustain the movement through these dark times? Finally, the paper presents a set of articles written in response to these questions: What, if any, should the ethical commitments of the P4C facilitator be? Is political/ideological neutrality required of the P4C facilitator? Is political neutrality possible? What constitutes indoctrination in educational settings? Are children more vulnerable to indoctrination than adults, and if so, what are the implications of that fact for the practice of P4C? What are the uses of P4C in the dramatically polarized ideological landscape we currently inhabit? What, if any, are the ethical responsibilities of a teacher engaging in philosophical practice? Are the philosophical practitioner’s ethical responsibilities similar or different when the subjects are children or adults? Does every methodology have a “hidden curriculum”? If so, what is the hidden curriculum of P4C? What distinguishes dialogical from monological practice? May one have the appearance of the other? Is the “Socratic method” as we conceive it dialogical? What, if any, are the uses of irony in philosophical practice? Should Socrates be considered a model for P4C practitioners?

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,202

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Importance of Listening to Philosophy that Comes from Children.Sofia Nikolidaki - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 43:95-100.
Learning to Operate with Philosophical Concepts.Karel van der Leeuw & Pieter Mostert - 1987 - Analytic Teaching and Philosophical Praxis 8 (1).
Philosophy for Children in China:: A Late Preliminary Anti-Report.David Kennedy & Walter Kohan - 2002 - Analytic Teaching and Philosophical Praxis 22 (1):37-49.
A first name basis?David Benatar - 2011 - Think 10 (29):51-57.
Can children do philosophy?Karin Murris - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (2):261–279.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-11-20

Downloads
32 (#471,613)

6 months
16 (#136,207)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Walter Kohan
Rio de Janeiro State University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references