Modelling and representing: An artefactual approach to model-based representation

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (2):262-271 (2011)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The recent discussion on scientific representation has focused on models and their relationship to the real world. It has been assumed that models give us knowledge because they represent their supposed real target systems. However, here agreement among philosophers of science has tended to end as they have presented widely different views on how representation should be understood. I will argue that the traditional representational approach is too limiting as regards the epistemic value of modelling given the focus on the relationship between a single model and its supposed target system, and the neglect of the actual representational means with which scientists construct models. I therefore suggest an alternative account of models as epistemic tools. This amounts to regarding them as concrete artefacts that are built by specific representational means and are constrained by their design in such a way that they facilitate the study of certain scientific questions, and learning from them by means of construction and manipulation.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 80,057

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

How do models give us knowledge? The case of Carnot’s ideal heat engine.Tarja Knuuttila & Mieke Boon - 2011 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (3):309-334.
On qualitative modelling.Jarmo J. Ahonen - 1994 - AI and Society 8 (1):17-28.
Mental representation from the bottom up.Dan Lloyd - 1987 - Synthese 70 (January):23-78.
Complexity and scientific modelling.Bruce Edmonds - 2000 - Foundations of Science 5 (3):379-390.
Representing and Knowing.David Michael Banach - 1987 - Dissertation, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale
Structural Modelling, Exogeneity, and Causality.Federica Russo, Michel Mouchart & Guillaume Wunsch - 2009 - In Causal Analysis in Population Studies. pp. 59-82.
An object model for use in oral and written advocacy.Charles Unwin - 2008 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 16 (4):389-402.
Models, Representation, and Mediation.Tarja Knuuttila - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):1260-1271.
Scientific representation.Mauricio Suárez - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (1):91-101.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-06-11

Downloads
564 (#19,688)

6 months
6 (#144,544)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Tarja Knuuttila
University of Vienna

Citations of this work

Model Pluralism.Walter Veit - 2019 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 50 (2):91-114.
Data models, representation and adequacy-for-purpose.Alisa Bokulich & Wendy Parker - 2021 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 (1):1-26.
The New Fiction View of Models.Fiora Salis - 2021 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 72 (3):717-742.
Scientific representation.Roman Frigg & James Nguyen - 2016 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

View all 109 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Three Kinds of Idealization.Michael Weisberg - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy 104 (12):639-659.
How models are used to represent reality.Ronald N. Giere - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):742-752.
The strategy of model-based science.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 2006 - Biology and Philosophy 21 (5):725-740.
Who is a Modeler?Michael Weisberg - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (2):207-233.
Fundamental aspects of cognitive representation.Stephen Palmer - 1978 - In Eleanor Rosch & Barbara Lloyd (eds.), Cognition and Categorization. Lawrence Elbaum Associates. pp. 259-303.

View all 58 references / Add more references