Philosophy and Social Criticism 43 (4-5):453-464 (2017)

Authors
Cristina Lafont
Northwestern University
Abstract
The normative place of religion in liberal democracies is as contested as ever. This contestation produces understandable fears that liberal democratic institutions may ultimately be incompatible with religious forms of life. If this is so, if there is genuinely no hope that secular and religious citizens can equally take ownership over and identify with these institutions, then the future of democracy within pluralist societies seems seriously threatened. These fears commonly arise in debates concerning the liberal criterion of democratic legitimacy, according to which citizens ought to justify the imposition of coercive policies on each other with reasons that everyone can reasonably accept. Since religious reasons are not generally acceptable to secular citizens and citizens of different faiths, endorsing this criterion entails accepting the claim that, for the purposes of political justification, public reasons should take priority over religious considerations. This claim has been vigorously criticized on two grounds. First, critics resist such a claim on the skeptical grounds that there is simply no such thing as public reasons, that is, a subset of reasons that all citizens can reasonably accept as having priority for justifying coercive policies. Second, critics contest the claim on the normative grounds that an unequal treatment of religious reasons for the purposes of political justification is unfair to religious citizens and is therefore incompatible with the core values of a liberal democracy. Against both lines of criticism, I articulate a defense of the priority of public reasons that is exclusively based on the normative commitments constitutive of liberal democratic institutions and which can therefore be reflectively endorsed by all democratic citizens, whether religious or secular.
Keywords No keywords specified (fix it)
Categories No categories specified
(categorize this paper)
ISBN(s)
DOI 10.1177/0191453717695366
Options
Edit this record
Mark as duplicate
Export citation
Find it on Scholar
Request removal from index
Revision history

Download options

PhilArchive copy


Upload a copy of this paper     Check publisher's policy     Papers currently archived: 65,784
External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server
Configure custom proxy (use this if your affiliation does not provide a proxy)
Through your library

References found in this work BETA

No references found.

Add more references

Citations of this work BETA

No citations found.

Add more citations

Similar books and articles

Disrobing in the Oresteia.R. Drew Griffith - 1988 - Classical Quarterly 38 (02):552-.
Disrobing in the Oresteia.R. Drew Griffith - 1988 - Classical Quarterly 38 (2):552-554.
The Robes of Iphigeneia.Hugh Lloyd-Jones - 1952 - The Classical Review 2 (3-4):132-135.
S/T = Untitled (No Robes Las Flores Que Sembré Para Ti).Oscar Osmeivy Ortega - 2010 - In Steven C. Daiber & Yamilys Brito Jorge (eds.), Poder. Red Trillum Press.
Discovering Records Beneath the Robes.Amanda M. Pike - 2010 - Journal of Information Ethics 19 (1):86-98.
How Can a Society Make its Citizens Just?H. Lotter - 2001 - South African Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):91-101.
Imperial Robes and Textiles of the Chinese Court.Schuyler Cammann & Alan Priest - 1943 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 63 (4):295.
How Can a Society Make its Citizens Just?Hennie Lotter - 2001 - South African Journal of Philosophy 20 (1):90-101.
Pioneer Black Robes of the West Coast.Jerome V. Jacobsen - 1942 - Thought: Fordham University Quarterly 17 (2):367-368.
Partnership of Citizens and Metics: The Will of Epicurus.M. Leiwo & P. Remes - 1999 - Classical Quarterly 49 (01):161-166.

Analytics

Added to PP index
2017-04-06

Total views
15 ( #683,604 of 2,463,159 )

Recent downloads (6 months)
1 ( #449,391 of 2,463,159 )

How can I increase my downloads?

Downloads

My notes