On complicity and compromise: a reply

Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (4):277-278 (2017)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The cautions of our commentators are all well taken, and we are grateful for them. When we say that physicians should respect the wishes of their patients for medical treatment, even if that would make them complicit in torture being inflicted on their patients, Henry Shue reminds us that that assumes that the patients undergoing torture retain minimally adequate decision-making capacity. Insofar as the torture aims at, and succeeds in, producing ‘regression to an infantile state’, patients who are victims of such torture would likely fail standard tests of that. True though that observation may be, it leaves us with no solution to our initial problem. Were we to assume that the victim does not have decision-making capacity, and reject his request for treatment on that basis, we would victimise him further by abandoning him to his fate leaving him with no alternatives and no support whatsoever. Furthermore, in regimes of psychologically sophisticated torture of the sort Shue discusses, there may be an even stronger reason for a physician to comply with a victim-patient's request for her to treat him. For a physician to refuse a would-be patient's request for treatment, on grounds he lacks adequate decision-making capacity, might further reinforce the infantilising message of the torturers. If so, that would amount to complicity in his torture, insofar as it furthers the wrong done by perpetrators. In the absence of victim's consent, doctors typically use criteria like family's advice, patient's best interest or heuristics identifying what most patients would prefer in similar situations. None of these options is available to doctors caring for torture survivors during the course of their torture, however. The first is obviously not. The second is not because the physician cannot be altogether sure what is in her victim-patient's best interests, given that treating him will …

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,423

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

On complicity and compromise.Chiara Lepora - 2013 - Oxford United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. Edited by Robert E. Goodin.
On complicity and compromise: a précis.Chiara Lepora & Robert E. Goodin - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (4):269-269.
Complicity: That Moral Monster, Troubling Matters.Peter A. French - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (3):575-589.
Grading Complicity in Rwandan Refugee Camps.Chiara Lepora & Robert E. Goodin - 2011 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 28 (3):259-276.
On Complicity and Compromise. [REVIEW]Hugo Slim - 2013 - Ethics and International Affairs 27 (4):467-469.
Complicity and Compromise in the Law of Nations.Steven R. Ratner - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (3):559-573.
Can a compromise be fair?Peter Jones & Ian O’Flynn - 2013 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 12 (2):115-135.
Consumer Complicity and Labor Exploitation.Gillian Brock - 2016 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 16 (1):113-125.
Compromise: a political and philosophical history.Alin Fumurescu - 2013 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
On Compromise and Being Compromised.Chiara Lepora - 2012 - Journal of Political Philosophy 20 (1):1-22.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-03-26

Downloads
39 (#399,999)

6 months
7 (#418,426)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Chiara Lepora
University of Denver
Robert Goodin
Australian National University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Defensive Killing.Helen Frowe - 2014 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Individual Complicity: The Tortured Patient.Chiara Lepora - 2013 - In On complicity and compromise. Oxford United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.

Add more references