Game as Paradox: A Rebuttal of Suits
Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39 (1):155-168 (2012)
Abstract
Here I examine Bernard Suits?s definition of games and explain why that definition is in need of reference to representation or, put more generally, to semiosis. And, once admitting the necessity of the representational in games, Suits?s definition must also then admit the essential paradoxy of gamesDOI
10.1080/00948705.2012.675071
My notes
Similar books and articles
Suits, Autotelicity, Temporal Reallocations, Game Resources and Defining 'play'.Richard Royce - 2011 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 5 (2):93 - 109.
The Lottery Paradox Generalized?Jake Chandler - 2010 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61 (3):667-679.
The Paradox of the Knower without Epistemic Closure -- Corrected.C. B. Cross - 2012 - Mind 121 (482):457-466.
The lesson of Newcomb’s paradox.David H. Wolpert & Gregory Benford - 2013 - Synthese 190 (9):1637-1646.
More on the paradox of the knower without epistemic closure.Charles B. Cross - 2004 - Mind 113 (449):109-114.
Newcomb’s Paradox Realized with Backward Causation.Jan Hendrik Schmidt - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (1):67-87.
Analytics
Added to PP
2013-10-31
Downloads
42 (#280,216)
6 months
1 (#450,425)
2013-10-31
Downloads
42 (#280,216)
6 months
1 (#450,425)
Historical graph of downloads
Citations of this work
The Paradoxes of Utopian Game-Playing.Deborah P. Vossen - 2017 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 44 (3):315-328.
Playing with Art in Suits’ Utopia.Nathan Wildman & Alfred Archer - 2019 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 13 (3-4):456-470.
An Epistemic Condition for Playing a Game.Lukas Schwengerer - 2018 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 13 (3-4):293-306.
References found in this work
Triad Trickery: Playing With Sport and Games.Klaus V. Meier - 1988 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 15 (1):11-30.