Kybernetes 47:163-185 (2018)
Authors | |
Abstract |
Purpose – Neuroscientists act as proxies for implied anthropomorphic signal- processing beings within the brain, Homunculi. The latter examine the arriving neuronal spike-trains to infer internal and external states. But a Homunculus needs a brain of its own, to coordinate its capabilities – a brain that necessarily contains a Homunculus and so on indefinitely. Such infinity is impossible – and in well-cited papers, Attneave and later Dennett claim to eliminate it. How do their approaches differ and do they (in fact) obviate the Homunculi?
Design/methodology/approach – The Attneave and Dennett approaches are carefully scrutinized. To Attneave, Homunculi are effectively “decision-making” neurons that control behaviors. Attneave presumes that Homunculi, when successively nested, become successively “stupider”, limiting their numbers by diminishing their responsibilities. Dennett likewise postulates neuronal Homunculi that become “stupider” – but brain-wards, where greater sophistication might have been expected.
Findings – Attneave’s argument is Reductionist and it simply assumes-away the Homuncular infinity. Dennett’s scheme, which evidently derives from Attneave’s, ultimately involves the same mistakes. Attneave and Dennett fail, because they attempt to reduce intentionality to non-intentionality.
Research limitations/implications – Homunculus has been successively recognized over the centuries by philosophers, psychologists and (some) neuroscientists as a crucial conundrum of cognitive science. It still is.
Practical implications – Cognitive-science researchers need to recognize that Reductionist explanations of cognition may actually devolve to Homunculi, rather than eliminating them.
Originality/value – Two notable Reductionist arguments against the infinity of Homunculi are proven wrong. In their place, a non-Reductionist treatment of the mind, “Emergence”, is discussed as a means of rendering Homunculi irrelevant.
|
Keywords | Brain Homunculus Neuron Reductionism Attneave Dennett |
Categories | (categorize this paper) |
Options |
![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Download options
References found in this work BETA
What is It Like to Be a Bat?Thomas Nagel - 2004 - In Tim Crane & Katalin Farkas (eds.), Metaphysics: A Guide and Anthology. Oxford University Press.
The Cognitive Neuroscience Revolution.Worth Boone & Gualtiero Piccinini - 2016 - Synthese 193 (5):1509-1534.
View all 31 references / Add more references
Citations of this work BETA
No citations found.
Similar books and articles
Homunculus Strides Again: Why ‘Information Transmitted’ in Neuroscience Tells Us Nothing.Lance Nizami - 2015 - Kybernetes 44:1358-1370.
What is It Like to Be a Homunculus?Stephen L. White - 1987 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 68 (June):148-74.
Aston-Jones, G. 269, 272 Atkinson, JW 201.F. Attneave, C. Akerman, H. L. Alderson, L. A. Alfonso-Reese, G. F. Alheid, M. T. Alkire, L. G. Allan, D. A. Allport, P. Alvarez-Royo & D. G. Amaral - 2002 - In Simon C. Moore (ed.), Emotional Cognition: From Brain to Behaviour. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. pp. 317.
A Closer Look at the Chinese Nation Argument.Erdinç Sayan - 1987 - Philosophy Research Archives 13:129-36.
Interview with Daniel Dennett Conducted by Bill Uzgalis in␣Boston, Massachusetts on December 29, 2004.Bill Uzgalis - 2006 - Minds and Machines 16 (1):7-19.
Toward a Distributed Computation Model of Extended Cognition.Thomas W. Polger - 2010 - APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers, 10 (1):16-20.
How is Block’s Central Argument Against Functionalism?zg ma - 2018 - Asian Research Journal of Arts and Social Sciences 5 (1):01-04.
What RoboDennett Still Doesn't Know.Michael Beaton - 2005 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 12 (12):3-25.
Analytics
Added to PP index
2018-12-29
Total views
126 ( #91,591 of 2,499,389 )
Recent downloads (6 months)
25 ( #34,863 of 2,499,389 )
2018-12-29
Total views
126 ( #91,591 of 2,499,389 )
Recent downloads (6 months)
25 ( #34,863 of 2,499,389 )
How can I increase my downloads?
Downloads