Skepticism, Invulnerability, and Epistemological Dissatisfaction

In C. Illies & C. Schaefer (eds.), Metaphysics or Modernity? Bamberg University Press. pp. 113-148 (2013)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

How should we understand the relationship between the contents of our color, causal, modal, and evaluative beliefs, on the one hand, and color, causal, modal, and evaluative properties, on the other? According to Barry Stroud (2011), because of the nature of the contents of those types of beliefs, we should also think that what he calls a “negative metaphysical verdict” on the latter is not one that we could consistently maintain. The metaphysical project aims to arrive at an improved conception of ourselves and our relation the world, no matter if that conception is positive or negative. But if Stroud is right that we cannot consistently arrive at the view that all of our causal, modal, and evaluative beliefs are systematically false, we will see that we cannot consistently reach the negative verdict. But failure to reach the negative verdict doesn’t mean that we have reached the positive verdict. Stroud calls this philosophical failure “metaphysical dissatisfaction”. In this paper, I argue that we can appropriate a metaepistemological response to the problem of the external world which shares its core features with Stroud’s (2000, 2011) arguments, but which nevertheless leaves us with a distinctive kind of epistemological dissatisfaction.

Links

PhilArchive

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Modest transcendental arguments.Anthony Brueckner - 1996 - Philosophical Perspectives 10:265-280.
Transcendental arguments and 'epistemological naturalism'.Barry Stroud - 1977 - Philosophical Studies 31 (2):105 - 115.
Epistemological reflection on knowledge of the external world.Review author[S.]: Barry Stroud - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2):345-358.
Epistemological Realism as the Skeptic’s Heart of Darkness.Ron Wilburn - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Research 23:165-217.
Davidson’s Transcendental Externalism.Jason Bridges - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2):290-315.
Scepticism and its sources.Samir Okasha - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (3):610–632.
The significance of philosophical scepticism.Barry Stroud - 1984 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Davidson's Epistemology.Ernest Sosa - 2003 - In Kirk Ludwig (ed.), Contemporary Philosophy in Focus: Donald Davidson. Cambridge University Press.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-07-21

Downloads
1,591 (#4,450)

6 months
94 (#15,880)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Christopher Ranalli
VU University Amsterdam

Citations of this work

Radical Scepticism, How-Possible Questions and Modest Transcendental Arguments.Ju Wang - 2017 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 25 (2):210-226.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. Quine - 1951 - [Longmans, Green].
What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (October):435-50.
Essence and modality.Kit Fine - 1994 - Philosophical Perspectives 8 (Logic and Language):1-16.
The skeptic and the dogmatist.James Pryor - 2000 - Noûs 34 (4):517–549.
A confutation of convergent realism.Larry Laudan - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (1):19-49.

View all 74 references / Add more references