Law and Philosophy 31 (6):725-752 (2012)

Abstract
Kelsen advanced a sophisticated naturalist conception of intention and adumbrated a methodological strategy that would enable the transformation of the sophisticated naturalist conception of ‘intention’ into a cognizable object of legal science while simultaneously providing an explanation of the legal ‘ought’. The methodological strategy is the ‘inversion thesis’ which establishes that legal norms enable us to objectively identify and determine the ‘will’ or the intention of legal authority. Contrary to nineteenth century psychologism, Kelsen argues that it is not the case that the will or the intention of the sovereign determines what the norm is, rather it is the legal ought that ‘objectifies’ the will. However, it is argued that in spite of the fact that Kelsen advanced a sophisticated account of intentional action, he fails to understand the complexities of the notion of the ‘will’, intentional action and practical reason. What does he miss in his understanding of the notion of the practical? I will advance the view that the notion of the practical or deliberative involves, both in Kant and Aristotle, the transparency condition which establishes that the agent or deliberator intentionally acts for reasons that are self-evident or transparent to him or her. It is a recalcitrant feature of the deliberative standpoint that cannot be theorised. For Aristotle, Aquinas and Anscombe the deliberative standpoint can be known through the end or goal of the intentional action as this provides the form of the action. The end is presented as a good-making characteristic. As problematic as that might be, this means that the end needs to be presented as a good-making characteristic and therefore it involves evaluation. For Kelsen, the soundness of this conception is an insurmountable obstacle to theorise the ‘ought’ and therefore the ‘will’. Yet, surprisingly and contrary to Kelsen’s own notions, I will show that Kelsen’s ‘inversion thesis’ is parasitic on Aristotle–Anscombe’s ‘ought’.
Keywords Legal 'ought'  Practical reason and law  Anscombe's philosophy of action  law under the guise of the good
Categories (categorize this paper)
ISBN(s)
DOI 10.1007/s10982-012-9136-3
Options
Edit this record
Mark as duplicate
Export citation
Find it on Scholar
Request removal from index
Revision history

Download options

PhilArchive copy


Upload a copy of this paper     Check publisher's policy     Papers currently archived: 60,992
External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server
Configure custom proxy (use this if your affiliation does not provide a proxy)
Through your library

References found in this work BETA

Moran on Self‐Knowledge.Sydney Shoemaker - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):391-401.
Self-Knowledge, Responsibility, and the Third Person.Bernard Reginster - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (2):433-439.

Add more references

Citations of this work BETA

No citations found.

Add more citations

Similar books and articles

Kelsen's Concept of the Authority of Law.Bruno Celano - 2000 - Law and Philosophy 19 (2):173-199.
Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good.Sergio Tenenbaum (ed.) - 2010 - Oxford University Press.
General Theory of Norms.Hans Kelsen - 1990 - Oxford University Press.
Continuity and Change in Legal Positivism.M. H. & G. W. - 1998 - Law and Philosophy 17 (3):233-250.
Continuity and Change in Legal Positivism.Huib M. De Jong & Wouter G. Werner - 1998 - Law and Philosophy 17 (3):233 - 250.
Kelsen, Quietism, and the Rule of Recognition.Michael Steven Green - 2008 - In Matthew D. Adler & Kenneth E. Himma (eds.), THE RULE OF RECOGNITION AND THE UNITED STATES CONSTITUTION. Oxford University Press.
Authority and Authorisation.B. Roermund - 2000 - Law and Philosophy 19 (2):201-222.

Analytics

Added to PP index
2012-08-28

Total views
54 ( #192,547 of 2,439,431 )

Recent downloads (6 months)
1 ( #433,565 of 2,439,431 )

How can I increase my downloads?

Downloads

My notes