The pregnant woman and the good samaritan: Can a woman have a duty to undergo a caesarean section?

Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20 (3):407-436 (2000)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Although a pregnant woman can now refuse any medical treatment needed by the fetus, the Court of Appeal has acknowledged that ethical dilemmas remain, adverting to the inappropriateness of legal compulsion of presumed moral duties in this context. This leaves the impression of an uncomfortable split between the ethics and the law. The notion of a pregnant woman refusing medical treatment needed by the fetus is troubling and it helps little simply to assert that she has a legal right to do so. At the same time, the idea that a pregnant woman fails in her moral duty unless she accepts any recommended treatment or surgery—however great the burdens—is also not without difficulty. This article seeks to find a way between these two somewhat polarized positions by arguing that, instead of being a question primarily about whether legally to enforce moral obligations, the «maternal—fetal conflict» begins with previously unrecognized difficulties in determining when a woman's prima facie moral rights invoked in the treatment context should «give way» to the interests of the fetus. This difficulty is mirrored within the law. Thus, how can we tell when a pregnant woman has the moral or legal duty to submit to a caesarean section? Seen in this way, the conflict is a problem which lies at the interface between moral and legal rights and duties, showing that there are important conceptual links between the ethics and the law. Against this background, this article explores the limits of a pregnant woman's right to bodily integrity by focusing upon the idea of her moral duty to aid the fetus through her body. Here we find difficulties in determining the existence and extent of this somewhat extraordinary duty. Such a duty is contrasted with both negative and positive duties toward others in the course of «general conduct». Attention to the social context of pregnancy and the refusal of treatment within this is also instructive. Overall, the purpose is to foster understanding and acceptance of the current legal position

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Caesareans and Cyborgs.Hilary Lim - 1999 - Feminist Legal Studies 7 (2):133-173.
Abortion, Relationship, and Property in Labor: A Clinical Case Study.Donna Dickenson & Susan Bewley - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (4):440-448.
Women, forced caesareans and antenatal responsibilities.H. Draper - 1996 - Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (6):327-333.
Abortion: Three Rival Versions of Suffering.John Portmann - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (4):489-497.
The Samaritan Woman in India c.A.D. 200.J. Duncan M. Derrett - 1987 - Zeitschrift für Religions- Und Geistesgeschichte 39 (4):328-336.
Emotion.Maybelle Marie O. Padua - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 19:141-164.
The Decision to Abort.Rebecca Hanrahan - 2007 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 21 (1):25-41.
Natural deduction rules for English.Frederic B. Fitch - 1973 - Philosophical Studies 24 (2):89 - 104.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
38 (#409,607)

6 months
9 (#290,637)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

References found in this work

A defense of abortion.Judith Jarvis Thomson - 1971 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1):47-66.
The rights and wrongs of abortion: A reply to Judith Thomson.John Finnis - 1973 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 (2):117-145.
Feminist transformations of moral theory.Virginia Held - 1990 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50:321-344.

View all 8 references / Add more references