The silence of the norms: The missing historiography of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44 (4):545-552 (2013)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

History has been disparaged since the late 19th century for not conforming to norms of scientific explanation. Nonetheless, as a matter of fact a work of history upends the regnant philosophical conception of science in the second part of the 20th century. Yet despite its impact, Kuhn’s Structure has failed to motivate philosophers to ponder why works of history should be capable of exerting rational influence on an understanding of philosophy of science. But all this constitutes a great irony and a mystery. The mystery consists of the persistence of a complete lack of interest in efforts to theorize historical explanation. Fundamental questions regarding why an historical account could have any rational influence remain not merely unanswered, but unasked. The irony arises from the fact that analytic philosophy of history went into an eclipse where it remains until this day just around the time that the influence of Kuhn’s great work began to make itself felt. This paper highlights puzzles long ignored regarding the challenges a work of history managed to pose to the epistemic authority of science, and what this might imply generally for the place of philosophy of history vis-à-vis the problems of philosophy.

Other Versions

No versions found

Similar books and articles

The philosophical structure of historical explanation.Paul Andrew Roth - 2020 - Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.
Kuhn’s wrong turning.Alexander Bird - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (3):443-463.
Thomas Kuhn's revolutions: a historical and an evolutionary philosophy of science?James A. Marcum - 2015 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc.
Thomas Kuhn.Alexander Bird - 2000 - Routledge.
Between History and Philosophy of Science: The Relationship between Kuhn’s Black-Body Theory and Structure.Adam Timmins - 2019 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 9 (2):371-387.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-10-19

Downloads
893 (#29,010)

6 months
157 (#33,062)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Paul A. Roth
University of California, Santa Cruz

Citations of this work

Positivist or post-positivist philosophy of science? The left Vienna Circle and Thomas Kuhn.Joseph Bentley - 2024 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 107 (C):107-117.
Philosophy of History and History of Philosophy of Science.Thomas Uebel - 2017 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 7 (1):1-30.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
Epistemology Naturalized.W. V. Quine - 1969 - In Willard Van Orman Quine, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press.
The function of general laws in history.Carl Gustav Hempel - 1942 - Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):35-48.
Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning.Carl G. Hempel - 1950 - 11 Rev. Intern. De Philos 41 (11):41-63.

View all 18 references / Add more references