Ratio Juris 27 (1):21-46 (2014)
Abstract |
“Reason of state” is a concept that is rarely used in contemporary legal and political philosophy, compared to everyday parlance; “public reason,” in contrast, is ubiquitous, especially in liberal philosophy, as a legitimacy-conferring device. In this article it is argued that the unpopularity of the notion of “reason of state” is partly due to its notorious ambiguity. Three different usages of the notion can be identified: a “thin” usage (where “reason of state” is equivalent to the common good); an “ironical” usage (where it is used pejoratively to denounce it as a pretext for application of illegitimate or illegal means); and a “pre-emptive” usage (where “reason of state” functions as a legitimate second-order exclusionary reason used to override otherwise mandatory first-order rules of action). It is argued that only the “thin” usage is helpful in a by-and-large liberal-democratic context. The article then discusses the main dilemmas related to the concept of public reason, especially in its most influential, Rawlsian interpretation, and defends the concept against common critiques. Finally, the two concepts of “reason of state” and public reason are compared, and it is argued that a “thin” usage of “reason of state” is functionally equivalent to public reason, and that both resonate with the theory of “input democracy” (focusing, as it does, on the legitimacy of reasons—or motivations—for applying coercive rules to individuals). The article also identifies a problematic feature of “reason of state”: its emphasis on the state as a privileged interpreter of such reasons and/or as identifying the pool of actors within which the “constituency” of public reason is ascertained. There are good reasons to resist both of these consequences: the former because of its potentially authoritarian consequences, the latter because of reasons provided by cosmopolitan political conceptions
|
Keywords | No keywords specified (fix it) |
Categories | (categorize this paper) |
DOI | 10.1111/raju.12032 |
Options |
![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Download options
References found in this work BETA
View all 21 references / Add more references
Citations of this work BETA
The U.S. Congressional Record as a Technology of Representation.Zornitsa Keremidchieva - 2014 - Journal of Argumentation in Context 3 (1):57-82.
Similar books and articles
Public Reason Between Ethics and Law.José de Sousa E. Brito - 2012 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 25 (4):465-472.
Public Reason and Democracy.Andrew Lister - 2008 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 11 (3):273-289.
Enlightenment and Freedom.Jonathan Peterson - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (2):pp. 223-244.
Public Reason: Mediated Authority in the Liberal State.Fred M. Frohock - 1999 - Cornell University Press.
Against Public Reason Liberalism's Accessibility Requirement.Kevin Vallier - 2011 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (3):366-389.
Restraint on Reasons and Reasons for Restraint: A Problem for Rawls' Ideal of Public Reason.Micah Lott - 2006 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (1):75–95.
On Being Inside Social Morality and Seeing It.Gerald Gaus - 2015 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (1):141-153.
Rawls's Wide View of Public Reason: Not Wide Enough.David A. Reidy - 2000 - Res Publica 6 (1):49-72.
Public Reason as a Form of Normative and Political Justification: A Study on Rawls's Idea of Public Reason and Kant's Notion of the Use of Public Reason in What is Enlightenment?Paul Nnodim - 2004 - South African Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):148-157.
The Completeness of Public Reason.Micah Schwartzman - 2004 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 3 (2):191-220.
Analytics
Added to PP index
2014-02-16
Total views
17 ( #588,855 of 2,409,853 )
Recent downloads (6 months)
1 ( #541,271 of 2,409,853 )
2014-02-16
Total views
17 ( #588,855 of 2,409,853 )
Recent downloads (6 months)
1 ( #541,271 of 2,409,853 )
How can I increase my downloads?
Downloads