On deviant causal chains - no need for a general criterion

Analysis 69 (3):469-473 (2009)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Donald Davidson brought to our attention deviant causal chains as a problem for causal theories of action. Consider Davidson's own example: " A climber might want to rid himself of the weight and danger of holding another man on a rope, and he might know that by loosening his hold on the rope he could rid himself of the weight and danger. This belief and want might so unnerve him as to cause him to loosen his hold, and yet it might be the case that he never chose to loosen his hold, nor did he do it intentionally. " The loosening of the hold on the rope is an action, according to a simple causal theory of action earlier developed by Davidson , if we can describe it in a way that renders it intentional under that description. Is there a way of describing the climber's loosening of his hold of the rope as intentional? Did he intentionally loosen his hold? Well, his loosening his hold is both rationalized and explained causally with reference to the beliefs and desires held by the climber. But there seems to be something wrong with the causal chain.Is there a simple fix? Could we not say that even if the loosening of the hold on the rope is caused by a desire held by the climber it is not caused by any proximate desire of the climber ? Or, to give a new twist to this well-known argument, could we not say that the loosening of the hold on the rope is not caused in a way that is responsive to the desire? This latter idea has recently been suggested by Markus E. Schlosser as a simple solution to the …

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,122

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Non-deviant causal chains.Robert K. Shope - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Research 16:251-291.
The normative force of reasoning.Ralph Wedgwood - 2006 - Noûs 40 (4):660–686.
The Metaphysics of Rule-Following.Markus E. Schlosser - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 155 (3):345-369.
Deviant Causal Chains.Christopher Peacocke - 1979 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1):123 - 155.
Deviant Causal Chains.Dorothy Mitchell - 1982 - American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (4):351 - 353.
Basic deviance reconsidered.Markus E. Schlosser - 2007 - Analysis 67 (3):186–194.
Deviant Formal Causation.Sarah K. Paul - 2011 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 5 (3):1-24.
Deviant causal chains and non-basic action.Michael H. Robins - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):265 – 282.
Culpable Control and Deviant Causal Chains.Mark Alicke & David Rose - 2012 - Personality and Social Psychology Compass 6 (10):723-735.
Nondeviant Chains in Intentional Action.Robert K. Shope - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Research 21:15-49.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-07-01

Downloads
163 (#112,456)

6 months
12 (#157,869)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Torbjörn Tännsjö
Stockholm University

Citations of this work

The contours of control.Joshua Shepherd - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (3):395-411.
Mindlessness.Ezio Di Nucci - 2013 - Cambridge Scholars Press.
Action, Deviance, and Guidance.Ezio Di Nucci - 2013 - Abstracta (2):41-59.
The Deviance in Deviant Causal Chains.Neil McDonnell - 2015 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):162-170.

View all 8 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
Knowledge and Its Limits.Timothy Williamson - 2000 - Philosophy 76 (297):460-464.
Truth and other enigmas.Michael Dummett - 1978 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Knowledge and its Limits.Timothy Williamson - 2000 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 64 (1):200-201.
Knowledge and Its Limits.Timothy Williamson - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):452-458.

View all 23 references / Add more references