The fallacy of misplaced intentionality in social representation research

Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 24 (3):243–165 (1994)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This paper argues that social representations cannot be used as independent variables in causal explanations of social behaviour. It is shown that the structure of investigations often follows a causally explanatory design despite explicit statements to the contrary by the researchers. This fact is analyzed with three investigations. It is argued that verbal data used to assess the contents of a representation as independent variable are logically equivalent to data obtained from the “dependent” overt behaviour. Therefore these two kinds of data must be seen as two illustrations of the same representational contents. The researchers’preference for using verbal data to assess the independent variable and the tendency to introduce a causal relationship between representation and behaviour is shown to result from misplacing folk-beliefs. Folk-beliefs about intentional causality, it is shown, pertain to the same level as other beliefs about the world on the part of the subjects. Hence they are part of the folk-representation itself and must be treated as such; their use in scientific accounts of the belief-action relationship is not implied by data on rational belief systems. It is suggested to conceptualize social representations as integral units of beliefs and action which may be used to explain causally subsequent contingent social events. The function of folk-beliefs in intentional causality for the self-concept of rational people and for social accountability is discussed

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The Phenomenal Intentionality Research Program.Uriah Kriegel - 2013 - In U. Kriegel (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. pp. 1–26.
Motor intentionality and its primordiality.Jennifer Hudin - 2006 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 49 (6):573 – 590.
Intentionality and representation.Nicholas Georgalis - 1986 - International Studies in Philosophy 18 (3):45-58.
African philosophy and the sociological thesis.Carole Pearce - 1992 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 22 (4):440-460.
Collectives and intentionality.Jennifer Hornsby - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (2):429-434.
Intentionality, representation, and function.David Pickles - 1989 - Sussex University, Cognitive Science Research Paper 140.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
24 (#639,942)

6 months
4 (#790,687)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Queries about social representation and construction.Wolfgang Wagner - 1996 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 26 (2):95–120.
Everyday folk-politics, sensibleness and the explanation of action - an answer to cranach.Wolfgang Wagner - 1995 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 25 (3):295–301.
Social representations and mass communication research.Michel-Louis Rouquette - 1996 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 26 (2):221–231.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind.John R. Searle - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Meaning.Herbert Paul Grice - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (3):377-388.
Sour grapes: studies in the subversion of rationality.Jon Elster - 1983 - Paris: Editions de la Maison des sciences de l'homme.
Intentionality.J. Searle - 1983 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 49 (3):530-531.

View all 12 references / Add more references