Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex.Charles Darwin - 1898 - New York: Plume. Edited by Carl Zimmer.
  • Of identity and diversity (book II, chapter XXVII).John Locke - 1689 - In An essay concerning human understanding. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • The direction of time.Hans Reichenbach - 1956 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications. Edited by Maria Reichenbach.
    The final work of a distinguished physicist, this remarkable volume examines the emotive significance of time, the time order of mechanics, the time direction of thermodynamics and microstatistics, the time direction of macrostatistics, and the time of quantum physics. Coherent discussions include accounts of analytic methods of scientific philosophy in the investigation of probability, quantum mechanics, the theory of relativity, and causality. "[Reichenbach’s] best by a good deal."—Physics Today. 1971 ed.
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    In the course of the discussion, Professor Quine pinpoints the difficulties involved in translation, brings to light the anomalies and conflicts implicit in our ...
  • The Language of Thought.Jerry A. Fodor - 1975 - Harvard University Press.
    INTRODUCTION: TWO KINDS OF RLDUCTIONISM The man who laughs is the one who has not yet heard the terrible news. BERTHOLD BRECHT I propose, in this book, ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1648 citations  
  • Realism in Mathematics.Joan Weiner - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (2):281.
  • Précis of Elements of episodic memory.Endel Tulving - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):223.
  • Representation and Reality.Robert Stalnaker - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (2):359.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   249 citations  
  • The nature of discrimination learning in animals.K. W. Spence - 1936 - Psychological Review 43 (5):427-449.
  • On the proper treatment of connectionism.Paul Smolensky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):1-23.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   741 citations  
  • How brains make chaos in order to make sense of the world.Christine A. Skarda & Walter J. Freeman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):161-173.
  • On the Validity of Simulating Stagewise Development by Means of PDP Networks: Application of Catastrophe Analysis and an Experimental Test of Rule‐Like Network Performance.Maartje E. J. Raijmakers, Sylvester Koten & Peter C. M. Molenaar - 1996 - Cognitive Science 20 (1):101-136.
    This article addresses the ability of Parallel Distributed Processing (PDP) networks to generate stagewise cognitive development in accordance with Piaget's theory of cognitive epigenesis. We carried out a replication study of the simulation experiments by McClelland (1989) and McClelland and Jenkins (1991) in which a PDP network learns to solve balance scale problems. In objective tests motivated from catastrophe theory, a mathematical theory of transitions in epigenetical systems, no evidence for stage transitions in network performance was found. It is concluded (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundation of cognitive science.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):111-32.
    The computational view of mind rests on certain intuitions regarding the fundamental similarity between computation and cognition. We examine some of these intuitions and suggest that they derive from the fact that computers and human organisms are both physical systems whose behavior is correctly described as being governed by rules acting on symbolic representations. Some of the implications of this view are discussed. It is suggested that a fundamental hypothesis of this approach is that there is a natural domain of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   662 citations  
  • Representation and Reality.Hilary Putnam - 1987 - MIT Press.
    Hilary Putnam, who may have been the first philosopher to advance the notion that the computer is an apt model for the mind, takes a radically new view of his...
  • On language and connectionism: Analysis of a parallel distributed processing model of language acquisition.Steven Pinker & Alan Prince - 1988 - Cognition 28 (1-2):73-193.
  • Why Connectionism is Such a Good Thing. A Criticism of Fodor and Pylyshyn's Criticism of Smolensky.Jean Petitot - 1991 - Philosophica 47.
  • The cell assembly: Mark II.P. M. Milner - 1957 - Psychological Review 64 (4):242-252.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Review of T he Direction of Time.Henryk Mehlberg - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (1):99.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   226 citations  
  • Realism in mathematics.Penelope Maddy - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Prress.
    Mathematicians tend to think of themselves as scientists investigating the features of real mathematical things, and the wildly successful application of mathematics in the physical sciences reinforces this picture of mathematics as an objective study. For philosophers, however, this realism about mathematics raises serious questions: What are mathematical things? Where are they? How do we know about them? Offering a scrupulously fair treatment of both mathematical and philosophical concerns, Penelope Maddy here delineates and defends a novel version of mathematical realism. (...)
  • The relation between linguistic structure and associative theories of language learning—A constructive critique of some connectionist learning models.Joel Lachter & Thomas G. Bever - 1988 - Cognition 28 (1-2):195-247.
  • ALCOVE: An exemplar-based connectionist model of category learning.John K. Kruschke - 1992 - Psychological Review 99 (1):22-44.
  • Vertical and horizontal processes in problem solving.Howard H. Kendler & Tracy S. Kendler - 1962 - Psychological Review 69 (1):1-16.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • A comparison of reversal shifts and nonreversal shifts in human concept formation behavior.Howard H. Kendler & May F. D'Amato - 1955 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 49 (3):165.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Discrimination learning as a function of reversal and nonreversal shifts.Roger T. Kelleher - 1956 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 51 (6):379.
  • Active symbols and internal models: Towards a cognitive connectionism. [REVIEW]Stephen Kaplan, Mark Weaver & Robert French - 1990 - AI and Society 4 (1):51-71.
    In the first section of the article, we examine some recent criticisms of the connectionist enterprise: first, that connectionist models are fundamentally behaviorist in nature (and, therefore, non-cognitive), and second that connectionist models are fundamentally associationist in nature (and, therefore, cognitively weak). We argue that, for a limited class of connectionist models (feed-forward, pattern-associator models), the first criticism is unavoidable. With respect to the second criticism, we propose that connectionist modelsare fundamentally associationist but that this is appropriate for building models (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Competitive Learning: From Interactive Activation to Adaptive Resonance.Stephen Grossberg - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (1):23-63.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   245 citations  
  • Chaotic dynamics versus representationalism.Walter J. Freeman & Christine A. Skarda - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):167-168.
  • The Language of Thought.Patricia Smith Churchland - 1975 - Noûs 14 (1):120-124.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1274 citations  
  • Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: Why Smolensky's solution doesn't work.Jerry Fodor & Brian P. McLaughlin - 1990 - Cognition 35 (2):183-205.
  • Representation, similarity, and the chorus of prototypes.Shimon Edelman - 1995 - Minds and Machines 5 (1):45-68.
    It is proposed to conceive of representation as an emergent phenomenon that is supervenient on patterns of activity of coarsely tuned and highly redundant feature detectors. The computational underpinnings of the outlined concept of representation are (1) the properties of collections of overlapping graded receptive fields, as in the biological perceptual systems that exhibit hyperacuity-level performance, and (2) the sufficiency of a set of proximal distances between stimulus representations for the recovery of the corresponding distal contrasts between stimuli, as in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Meaning and Mental Representation.Robert Cummins - 1989 - MIT Press.
    Looks at accounts by Locke, Fodor, Dretske, and Millikan concerning the nature of mental representation, and discusses connectionism and representation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   285 citations  
  • Meaning and Mental Representation.Peter Carruthers - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161):527-530.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   186 citations  
  • Is there a role for extraretinal factors in the maintenance of stability in a structured environment?Eugene Chekaluk - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):258-258.
    The calibration solution to the stability of the world despite eye movements depends, according to Bridgeman et al., upon a combination of three factors which presumably all need to operate to achieve the goal of stability. Although the authors admit (sect. 4.3, para. 5) that the relative contributions of retinal and extraretinal factors will depend on the particular viewing situation, Figure 5 (sect. 4.3) makes it clear in its representation that the role of perceptual factors is relatively minor compared to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Reversal and nonreversal shifts in concept formation with partial reinforcement eliminated.Arnold H. Buss - 1956 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 52 (3):162.
  • A theory of visual stability across saccadic eye movements.Bruce Bridgeman, A. H. C. Van der Heijden & Boris M. Velichkovsky - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):247-258.
    We identify two aspects of the problem of maintaining perceptual stability despite an observer's eye movements. The first, visual direction constancy, is the (egocentric) stability of apparent positions of objects in the visual world relative to the perceiver. The second, visual position constancy, is the (exocentric) stability of positions of objects relative to each other. We analyze the constancy of visual direction despite saccadic eye movements.Three information sources have been proposed to enable the visual system to achieve stability: the structure (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Vehicles: Experiments in Synthetic Psychology.Valentino Braitenberg - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (1):137-139.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   171 citations  
  • Association, synonymity, and directionality in false recognition.Moshe Anisfeld & Margaret Knapp - 1968 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 77 (2):171.
  • Distinctive features, categorical perception, and probability learning: Some applications of a neural model.James A. Anderson, Jack W. Silverstein, Stephen A. Ritz & Randall S. Jones - 1977 - Psychological Review 84 (5):413-451.
  • Societies of Brains: A Study in the Neuroscience of Love and Hate.Walter J. Freeman - 1995 - Psychology Press.
    First Published in 1995. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • The Computer And The Brain.John Von Neumann - 1958 - New Haven: Yale University Press.
    This book represents the views of one of the greatest mathematicians of the twentieth century on the analogies between computing machines and the living human brain.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • The Direction of Time.Hans Reichenbach - 1956 - Philosophy 34 (128):65-66.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   416 citations  
  • Integrating connectionism and symbol manipulation: the importance of implementation.F. Van der Velde - forthcoming - Behavioral and Brain Sciences.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):278-279.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2801 citations  
  • Modèles mathématiques de la morphogenèse.René Thom - 1982 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 172 (3):556-564.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations