Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Meaning.Herbert Paul Grice - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (3):377-388.
  • A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs.Donald Davidson - 1986 - In Ernest LePore (ed.), Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 433--446.
    This essay argues that in linguistic communication, nothing corresponds to a linguistic competence as summarized by the three principles of first meaning in language: that first meaning is systematic, first meanings are shared, and first meanings are governed by learned conventions or regularities. There is no such a thing as a language, not if a language is anything like what many philosophers and linguists have supposed. We must give up the idea of a clearly defined shared structure which language users (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • Semantics and psychology.Scott Soames - 1985 - In Jerrold J. Katz (ed.), The Philosophy of linguistics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 204--226.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Reply to Foster.Donald Davidson - 1976 - In Gareth Evans & John Henry McDowell (eds.), Truth and meaning: essays in semantics. Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press. pp. 33--41.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Theories of meaning and speakers' knowledge.Crispin Wright - 2010 - In Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel (eds.), Arguing about language. New York: Routledge.
  • Meaning and truth theory.John Foster - 2010 - In Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel (eds.), Arguing about language. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The Varieties of Reference.Gareth Evans - 1982 - Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited by John Henry McDowell.
  • What every grammar does: A reply to prof. Arbini.Stephen P. Stich - 1973 - Philosophia 3 (1):85-96.
    Prof. Arbini's attention is flattering; his conclusions rather less so. The issues over which Arbini and I divide are many. Yet fundamentally, I think, our differences may be traced to disagreement about the nature and promise of the theories produced by contemporary generative grammarians. It is here that I shall focus my attention. Some of the points at which Arbini aims his criticism are quite crucial if we are to appreciate what sort of theory a grammar is. At other points (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What every speaker knows.Stephen P. Stich - 1971 - Philosophical Review 80 (4):476-496.
    The question I hope to answer is brief: What does every speaker of a natural language know? My answer is briefer still: Nothing, or at least nothing interesting. Explaining the question, and making the answer plausible, is a longer job.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • What every speaker cognizes.Stephen P. Stich - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):39-40.
  • Grammar, Psychology, and Indeterminacy.Stephen P. Stich - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (22):799-818.
    According to Quine, the linguist qua grammarian does not know what he is talking about. The goal of this essay is to tell him. My aim is to provide an account of what the grammarian is saying of an expression when he says it is grammatical, or a noun phrase, or ambiguous, or the subject of a certain sentence. More generally, I want to give an account of the nature of a generative grammatical theory of a language – of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Beliefs and subdoxastic states.Stephen P. Stich - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (December):499-518.
    It is argued that the intuitively sanctioned distinction between beliefs and non-belief states that play a role in the proximate causal history of beliefs is a distinction worth preserving in cognitive psychology. The intuitive distinction is argued to rest on a pair of features exhibited by beliefs but not by subdoxastic states. These are access to consciousness and inferential integration. Harman's view, which denies the distinction between beliefs and subdoxastic states, is discussed and criticized.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   311 citations  
  • Truth, meaning, and understanding.Scott Soames - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 65 (1-2):17-35.
  • The necessity argument.Scott Soames - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (5):575 - 580.
  • Linguistics and psychology.Scott Soames - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (2):155 - 179.
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Willard V. O. Quine - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):20–43.
    Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact, and truth which are synthetic, or grounded in fact. The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience. Both dogmas, I shall argue, are ill founded. One effect of abandoning them is, as (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1331 citations  
  • Methodological reflections on current linguistic theory.W. V. Quine - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):386-398.
  • A Study of Concepts.Christopher Peacocke - 1992 - MIT Press.
    Philosophers from Hume, Kant, and Wittgenstein to the recent realists and antirealists have sought to answer the question, What are concepts? This book provides a detailed, systematic, and accessible introduction to an original philosophical theory of concepts that Christopher Peacocke has developed in recent years to explain facts about the nature of thought, including its systematic character, its relations to truth and reference, and its normative dimension. Particular concepts are also treated within the general framework: perceptual concepts, logical concepts, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   695 citations  
  • Four philosophical problems of psycholinguists.George A. Miller - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (2):183-199.
    Four philosophical problems--predication, speech acts, rules, and innate ideas--are discussed in the light of their implications for psychological and linguistic research. The discussion of predication concerns both form and use. With respect to form, it is argued that our lexical memory is organized according to a predicate-argument formula that underlies the subject-predicate form of our sentences. With respect to use, it is argued that the illocutionary force of the sentence as a speech act must be taken into account. Both the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What model theoretic semantics cannot do?Ernest Lepore - 1983 - Synthese 54 (2):167 - 187.
  • What Davidson Should Have Said.Ernest LePore & Barry Loewer - 1989 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 36 (1):65-78.
    According to Davidson, a theory of meaning for a language L should specify information such that if someone had this information he would be in a position to understand L. He claims that a theory of truth for L fits this description. Many critics have argued that a truth theory is too weak to be a theory of meaning. We argue that these critics and Davidson's response to them have been misguided. Many critics have been misguided because they have not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What Davidson Should Have Said.Ernest LePore & Barry Loewer - 1989 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 36 (1):65-78.
    According to Davidson, a theory of meaning for a language L should specify information such that if someone had this information he would be in a position to understand L. He claims that a theory of truth for L fits this description. Many critics have argued that a truth theory is too weak to be a theory of meaning. We argue that these critics and Davidson's response to them have been misguided. Many critics have been misguided because they have not (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Translational semantics.Ernest Lepore & Barry Loewer - 1981 - Synthese 48 (1):121 - 133.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Truth and inference.Ernest Lepore - 1982 - Erkenntnis 18 (3):379 - 395.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Introduction.Ernest Lepore & Yi Jiang - 2014 - ProtoSociology 31:5-8.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • In defense of Davidson.Ernest Lepore - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (2):277 - 294.
  • Interpreted Logical Forms.Richard K. Larson & Peter Ludlow - 1993 - Synthese 95 (3):305 - 355.
  • Realism vs. conceptualism in linguistics.Jerrold J. Katz & Paul M. Postal - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (5):515 - 554.
  • Truth and understanding.James Higginbotham - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 65 (1-2):3 - 16.
  • Mind and language.Samuel D. Guttenplan (ed.) - 1975 - Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press.
  • Tacit knowledge.Christina Graves, Jerrold J. Katz, Yuji Nishiyama, Scott Soames, Robert Stecker & Peter Tovey - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (11):318-330.
  • Whence and Whither the Debate Between Quine and Chomsky?Alexander George - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy 83 (9):489.
  • The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanation.Jerry A. Fodor - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (October):627-40.
  • Concepts: a potboiler.Jerry Fodor - 1994 - Cognition 50 (1-3):95-113.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Concepts; A Potboiler.Jerry A. Fodor - 1995 - Philosophical Issues 6:1-24.
  • Linguistics: What's wrong with "the right view".Michael Devitt & Kim Sterelny - 1989 - Philosophical Perspectives 3:497-531.
  • Tacit knowledge and semantic theory: Can a five percent difference matter?Martin Davies - 1987 - Mind 96 (October):441-62.
    In his paper ‘Scmantic Theory and Tacit Knowlcdgc’, Gareth Evans uscs a familiar kind of cxamplc in ordcr to render vivid his account of tacit knowledge. We arc to consider a finite language, with just one hundrcd scntcnccs. Each scntcncc is made up of a subjcct (a name) and a prcdicatc. The names are ‘a’, ‘b’, . . ., T. The prcdicatcs arc ‘F’, ‘G’, . . ., ‘O’. Thc scntcnccs have meanings which dcpcnd in a systematic way upon their (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Truth and meaning.Donald Davidson - 1967 - Synthese 17 (1):304-323.
  • Radical interpretation.Donald Davidson - 1973 - Dialectica 27 (1):314-328.
  • Radical Interpretation.Donald Davidson - 1973 - Dialectica 27 (3-4):313-328.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   331 citations  
  • Connectionism, modularity, and tacit knowledge.Martin Davies - 1989 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (December):541-55.
    In this paper, I define tacit knowledge as a kind of causal-explanatory structure, mirroring the derivational structure in the theory that is tacitly known. On this definition, tacit knowledge does not have to be explicitly represented. I then take the notion of a modular theory, and project the idea of modularity to several different levels of description: in particular, to the processing level and the neurophysiological level. The fundamental description of a connectionist network lies at a level between the processing (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Belief and the basis of meaning.Donald Davidson - 1974 - Synthese 27 (July-August):309-323.
    A theory of radical interpretation gives the meanings of all sentences of a language, and can be verified by evidence available to someone who does not understand the language. Such evidence cannot include detailed information concerning the beliefs and intentions of speakers, and therefore the theory must simultaneously interpret the utterances of speakers and specify (some of) his beliefs. Analogies and connections with decision theory suggest the kind of theory that will serve for radical interpretation, and how permissible evidence can (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   171 citations  
  • Tacitness and virtual beliefs.Mark Crimmins - 1992 - Mind and Language 7 (3):240-63.
  • Knowledge of Language. [REVIEW]David Cooper - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (1):74-80.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Associative Engines: Connectionism, Concepts, and Representational Change.Andy Clark - 1993 - MIT Press.
    As Ruben notes, the macrostrategy can allow that the distinction may also be drawn at some micro level, but it insists that descent to the micro level is ...
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Rules and representations.Noam A. Chomsky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (127):1-61.
    The book from which these sections are excerpted is concerned with the prospects for assimilating the study of human intelligence and its products to the natural sciences through the investigation of cognitive structures, understood as systems of rules and representations that can be regarded as These mental structui′es serve as the vehicles for the exercise of various capacities. They develop in the mind on the basis of an innate endowment that permits the growth of rich and highly articulated structures along (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   958 citations  
  • Quine's empirical assumptions.Noam Chomsky - 1968 - Synthese 19 (1-2):53 - 68.
  • Language and nature.Noam Chomsky - 1995 - Mind 104 (413):1-61.
  • Philosophy of Language and Mind: 1950-1990.Tyler Burge - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (1):3.
  • On a confusion about a function of consciousness.Ned Block - 1995 - Brain and Behavioral Sciences 18 (2):227-–247.
    Consciousness is a mongrel concept: there are a number of very different "consciousnesses." Phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that state. The mark of access-consciousness, by contrast, is availability for use in reasoning and rationally guiding speech and action. These concepts are often partly or totally conflated, with bad results. This target article uses as an example a form of reasoning about a function of "consciousness" based on (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1123 citations