Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Frege's theory of numbers.Charles Parsons - 1964 - In Max Black (ed.), Philosophy in America. Ithaca: Routledge. pp. 180-203.
  • The basic laws of arithmetic.Gottlob Frege - 1893 - Berkeley,: University of California Press. Edited by Montgomery Furth.
    ... as 'logicism') that the content expressed by true propositions of arithmetic and analysis is not something of an irreducibly mathematical character, ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Frege's conception of numbers as objects.Crispin Wright - 1983 - [Aberdeen]: Aberdeen University Press.
  • Extensions as representative objects in Frege's logic.Marco Ruffino - 2000 - Erkenntnis 52 (2):239-252.
    Matthias Schirn has argued on a number of occasions against the interpretation of Frege's ``objects of a quite special kind'' (i.e., the objects referred to by names like `the concept F') as extensions of concepts. According to Schirn, not only are these objects not extensions, but also the idea that `the concept F' refers to objects leads to some conclusions that are counter-intuitive and incompatible with Frege's thought. In this paper, I challenge Schirn's conclusion: I want to try and argue (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Julius Caesar and Basic Law V.Richard G. Heck - 2005 - Dialectica 59 (2):161–178.
    This paper dates from about 1994: I rediscovered it on my hard drive in the spring of 2002. It represents an early attempt to explore the connections between the Julius Caesar problem and Frege's attitude towards Basic Law V. Most of the issues discussed here are ones treated rather differently in my more recent papers "The Julius Caesar Objection" and "Grundgesetze der Arithmetik I 10". But the treatment here is more accessible, in many ways, providing more context and a better (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Grundgesetze der arithmetic I §10.Richard Heck - 1999 - Philosophia Mathematica 7 (3):258-292.
    In section 10 of Grundgesetze, Frege confronts an indeterm inacy left by his stipulations regarding his ‘smooth breathing’, from which names of valueranges are formed. Though there has been much discussion of his arguments, it remains unclear what this indeterminacy is; why it bothers Frege; and how he proposes to respond to it. The present paper attempts to answer these questions by reading section 10 as preparatory for the (fallacious) proof, given in section 31, that every expression of Frege's formal (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Grundgesetze der Arithmetik I §§29‒32.Richard G. Heck - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (3):437-474.
    Frege's intention in section 31 of Grundgesetze is to show that every well-formed expression in his formal system denotes. But it has been obscure why he wants to do this and how he intends to do it. It is argued here that, in large part, Frege's purpose is to show that the smooth breathing, from which names of value-ranges are formed, denotes; that his proof that his other primitive expressions denote is sound and anticipates Tarski's theory of truth; and that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A model-theoretic reconstruction of Frege's permutation argument.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 1987 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (1):69-79.
  • Referentiality in Frege's Grundgesetze.Martin Edward - 1982 - History and Philosophy of Logic 3 (2):151-164.
    In §§28-31 of his Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Frege forwards a demonstration that every correctly formed name of his formal language has a reference. Examination of this demonstration, it is here argued, reveals an incompleteness in a procedure of contextual definition. At the heart of this incompleteness is a difference between Frege's criteria of referentiality and the possession of reference as it is ordinarily conceived. This difference relates to the distinction between objectual and substitutional quantification and Frege?s vacillation between the two.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Referentiality in frege's grundgesetze.Edward Martin Jr - 1982 - History and Philosophy of Logic 3 (2):151-164.
    In §§28-31 of his Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Frege forwards a demonstration that every correctly formed name of his formal language has a reference. Examination of this demonstration, it is here argued, reveals an incompleteness in a procedure of contextual definition. At the heart of this incompleteness is a difference between Frege’s criteria of referentiality and the possession of reference as it is ordinarily conceived. This difference relates to the distinction between objectual and substitutional quantification and Frege’s vacillation between the two.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • To be is to be an F.Øystein Linnebo - 2005 - Dialectica 59 (2):201–222.
    I defend the view that our ontology divides into categories, each with its own canonical way of identifying and distinguishing the objects it encompasses. For instance, I argue that natural numbers are identified and distinguished by their positions in the number sequence, and physical bodies, by facts having to do with spatiotemporal continuity. I also argue that objects belonging to different categories are ipso facto distinct. My arguments are based on an analysis of reference, which ascribes to reference a richer (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • To Be Is to Be an F.Øystein Linnebo - 2005 - Dialectica 59 (2):201-222.
    I defend the view that our ontology divides into categories, each with its own canonical way of identifying and distinguishing the objects it encompasses. For instance, I argue that natural numbers are identified and distinguished by their positions in the number sequence, and physical bodies, by facts having to do with spatiotemporal continuity. I also argue that objects belonging to different categories are ipso facto distinct. My arguments are based on an analysis of reference, which ascribes to reference a richer (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Frege's proof of referentiality.Øystein Linnebo - 2004 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 45 (2):73-98.
    I present a novel interpretation of Frege’s attempt at Grundgesetze I §§29-31 to prove that every expression of his language has a unique reference. I argue that Frege’s proof is based on a contextual account of reference, similar to but more sophisticated than that enshrined in his famous Context Principle. Although Frege’s proof is incorrect, I argue that the account of reference on which it is based is of potential philosophical value, and I analyze the class of cases to which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Caesar from Frege's Perspective.Gary Kemp - 2005 - Dialectica 59 (2):179-199.
    I attempt to explain Frege's handling of the Julius Caesar issue in terms of his more general philosophical commitments. These only became fully explicit in his middle-period writings, but his earlier moves are best explained, I suggest, if we suppose them to be implicit in his earlier thinking. These commitments conditionally justify Frege in rejecting Hume's Principle as either a definition or axiom but in accepting Axiom V. However, the general epistemological picture they constitute has serious problems in accounting for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Skeleton in Frege's Cupboard: The Standard Versus Nonstandard Distinction.Jaakko Hintikka & Gabriel Sandu - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy 89 (6):290.
  • What is Frege's Julius caesar problem?Dirk Greimann - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (3):261-278.
    This paper aims to determine what kind of problem Frege's famous “Julius Caesar problem” is. whether it is to be understood as the metaphysical problem of determining what kind of things abstract objects like numbers or value‐courses are, or as the epistemological problem of providing a means of recognizing these objects as the same again, or as the logical problem of providing abstract sortal concepts with a sharp delimitation in order to fulfill the law of excluded middle, or as the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Translations From the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege.Peter Geach & Max Black - 1952 - Philosophical Library.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Frege. [REVIEW]Michael D. Resnik - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4):961-963.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Frege on extensions of concepts, from 1884 to 1903.Tyler Burge - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (1):3-34.
  • Frege's permutation argument.A. W. Moore & Andrew Rein - 1987 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (1):51-54.
  • Frege's Notations: What They Are and How They Mean.Gregory Landini - 2011 - London and Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Gregory Landini offers a detailed historical account of Frege's notations and the philosophical views that led Frege from Begriffssscrhrift to his mature work Grundgesetze, addressing controversial issues that surround the notations.
  • Grundgesetze, Section 10.Adrian W. Moore & Andrew Rein - 1986 - In L. Haaparanta & J. Hintikka (eds.), Frege Synthesized. D. Reidel Publishing Co.. pp. 375--384.
    This is a study of Frege's permutation argument in Part I, Section 10, of Frege's Basic Laws of Arithmetic.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Frege. [REVIEW]Michael D. Resnik - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4):961-963.
  • Frege. [REVIEW]Michael D. Resnik - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4):961-963.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Frege. [REVIEW]Charles Parsons - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):540-547.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Crispin Wright, Frege's Conception of Numbers as Objects. [REVIEW]Boguslaw Wolniewicz - 1986 - Studia Logica 45 (3):330-330.
    The book is an attempt at explaining to the nation the ideas of Frege's Grundlagen. It is wordy and trite, a paradigm case of a redundant piece of writing. The reader is advised to steer clear of it.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   177 citations  
  • Percursos de Valores e Indeterminação da Referência.Matthias Schirn - 2001 - Princípios 8 (9):36-48.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation